Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] Out. Para. 1/1

OF THE EFFECTS OF FEAR (FOUR ARTICLES)

 We must now consider the effects of fear: under which head there are 
four points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether fear causes contraction?

 (2) Whether it makes men suitable for counsel?

 (3) Whether it makes one tremble?

 (4) Whether it hinders action?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether fear causes contraction?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that fear does not cause contraction. For when 
contraction takes place, the heat and vital spirits are withdrawn 
inwardly. But accumulation of heat and vital spirits in the interior 
parts of the body, dilates the heart unto endeavors of daring, as may be 
seen in those who are angered: while the contrary happens in those who 
are afraid. Therefore fear does not cause contraction.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, when, as a result of contraction, the vital spirits and 
heat are accumulated in the interior parts, man cries out, as may be seen 
in those who are in pain. But those who fear utter nothing: on the 
contrary they lose their speech. Therefore fear does not cause 
contraction.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, shame is a kind of fear, as stated above (Q[41], A[4]). 
But "those who are ashamed blush," as Cicero (De Quaest. Tusc. iv, 8), 
and the Philosopher (Ethic. iv, 9) observe. But blushing is an 
indication, not of contraction, but of the reverse. Therefore contraction 
is not an effect of fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 23) that "fear is a 
power according to {systole}," i.e. contraction.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, As stated above (Q[28], A[5]), in the passions of the 
soul, the formal element is the movement of the appetitive power, while 
the bodily transmutation is the material element. Both of these are 
mutually proportionate; and consequently the bodily transmutation assumes 
a resemblance to and the very nature of the appetitive movement. Now, as 
to the appetitive movement of the soul, fear implies a certain 
contraction: the reason of which is that fear arises from the imagination 
of some threatening evil which is difficult to repel, as stated above 
(Q[41], A[2]). But that a thing be difficult to repel is due to lack of 
power, as stated above (Q[43], A[2]): and the weaker a power is, the 
fewer the things to which it extends. Wherefore from the very imagination 
that causes fear there ensues a certain contraction in the appetite. Thus 
we observe in one who is dying that nature withdraws inwardly, on account 
of the lack of power: and again we see the inhabitants of a city, when 
seized with fear, leave the outskirts, and, as far as possible, make for 
the inner quarters. It is in resemblance to this contraction, which 
pertains to the appetite of the soul, that in fear a similar contraction 
of heat and vital spirits towards the  inner parts takes place in regard 
to the body.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As the Philosopher says (De Problem. xxvii, 3), although in 
those who fear, the vital spirits recede from outer to the inner parts of 
the body, yet the movement of vital spirits is not the same in those who 
are angry and those who are afraid. For in those who are angry, by reason 
of the heat and subtlety of the vital spirits, which result from the 
craving for vengeance, the inward movement has an upward direction: 
wherefore the vital spirits and heat concentrate around the heart: the 
result being that an angry man is quick and brave in attacking. But in 
those who are afraid, on account of the condensation caused by cold, the 
vital spirits have a downward movement; the said cold being due to the 
imagined lack of power. Consequently the heat and vital spirits abandon 
the heart instead of concentrating around it: the result being that a man 
who is afraid is not quick to attack, but is more inclined to run away.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: To everyone that is in pain, whether man or animal, it is 
natural to use all possible means of repelling the harmful thing that 
causes pain but its presence: thus we observe that animals, when in pain, 
attack with their jaws or with their horns. Now the greatest help for all 
purposes, in animals, is heat and vital spirits: wherefore when they are 
in pain, their nature stores up the heat and vital spirits within them, 
in order to make use thereof in repelling the harmful object. Hence the 
Philosopher says (De Problem. xxvii, 9) when the vital spirits and heat 
are concentrated together within, they require to find a vent in the 
voice: for which reason those who are in pain can scarcely refrain from 
crying aloud. On the other hand, in those who are afraid, the internal 
heat and vital spirits move from the heart downwards, as stated above (ad 
1): wherefore fear hinders speech which ensues from the emission of the 
vital spirits in an upward direction through the mouth: the result being 
that fear makes its subject speechless. For this reason, too, fear "makes 
its subject tremble," as the Philosopher says (De Problem. xxvii, 1,6,7).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Mortal perils are contrary not only to the appetite of the 
soul, but also to nature. Consequently in such like fear, there is 
contraction not only in the appetite, but also in the corporeal nature: 
for when an animal is moved by the imagination of death, it experiences a 
contraction of heat towards the inner parts of the body, as though it 
were threatened by a natural death. Hence it is that "those who are in 
fear of death turn pale" (Ethic. iv, 9). But the evil that shame fears, 
is contrary, not to nature, but only to the appetite of the soul. 
Consequently there results a contraction in this appetite, but not in the 
corporeal nature; in fact, the soul, as though contracted in itself, is 
free to set the vital spirits and heat in movement, so that they spread 
to the outward parts of the body: the result being that those who are 
ashamed blush.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether fear makes one suitable for counsel? 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that fear does not make one suitable for counsel. 
For the same thing cannot be conducive to counsel, and a hindrance 
thereto. But fear hinders counsel: because every passion disturbs repose, 
which is requisite for the good use of reason. Therefore fear does not 
make a man suitable for counsel.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, counsel is an act of reason, in thinking and 
deliberating about the future. But a certain fear "drives away all 
thought, and dislocates the mind," as Cicero observes (De Quaest. Tusc. 
iv, 8). Therefore fear does not conduce to counsel, but hinders it.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, just as we have recourse to counsel in order to avoid 
evil, so do we, in order to attain good things. But whereas fear is of 
evil to be avoided, so is hope of good things to be obtained. Therefore 
fear is not more conducive to counsel, than hope is.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that "fear makes men 
of counsel."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, A man of counsel may be taken in two ways. First, from 
his being willing or anxious to take counsel. And thus fear makes men of 
counsel. Because, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. iii, 3), "we take 
counsel on great matters, because therein we distrust ourselves." Now 
things which make us afraid, are not simply evil, but have a certain 
magnitude, both because they seem difficult to repel, and because they 
are apprehended as near to us, as stated above (Q[42], A[2]). Wherefore 
men seek for counsel especially when they are afraid.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Body Para. 2/3

 Secondly, a man of counsel means one who is apt for giving good counsel: 
and in this sense, neither fear nor any passion makes men of counsel. 
Because when a man is affected by a passion, things seem to him greater 
or smaller than they really are: thus to a lover, what he loves seems 
better; to him that fears, what he fears seems more dreadful. 
Consequently owing to the want of right judgment, every passion, 
considered in itself, hinders the faculty of giving good counsel.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] Body Para. 3/3

 This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The stronger a passion is, the greater the hindrance is it 
to the man who is swayed by it. Consequently, when fear is intense, man 
does indeed wish to take counsel, but his thoughts are so disturbed, that 
he can find no counsel. If, however, the fear be slight, so as to make a 
man wish to take counsel, without gravely disturbing the reason; it may 
even make it easier for him to take good counsel, by reason of his 
ensuing carefulness.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Hope also makes man a good counsellor: because, as the 
Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5), "no man takes counsel in  matters he 
despairs of," nor about impossible things, as he says in Ethic. iii, 3. 
But fear incites to counsel more than hope does. Because hope is of good 
things, as being possible of attainment; whereas fear is of evil things, 
as being difficult to repel, so that fear regards the aspect of 
difficulty more than hope does. And it is in matters of difficulty, 
especially when we distrust ourselves, that we take counsel, as stated 
above.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether fear makes one tremble?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that trembling is not an effect of fear. Because 
trembling is occasioned by cold; thus we observe that a cold person 
trembles. Now fear does not seem to make one cold, but rather to cause a 
parching heat: a sign whereof is that those who fear are thirsty, 
especially if their fear be very great, as in the case of those who are 
being led to execution. Therefore fear does not cause trembling.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, faecal evacuation is occasioned by heat; hence laxative 
medicines are generally warm. But these evacuations are often caused by 
fear. Therefore fear apparently causes heat; and consequently does not 
cause trembling.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, in fear, the heat is withdrawn from the outer to the 
inner parts of the body. If, therefore, man trembles in his outward 
parts, through the heat being withdrawn thus; it seems that fear should 
cause this trembling in all the external members. But such is not the 
case. Therefore trembling of the body is not caused by fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Cicero says (De Quaest. Tusc. iv, 8) that "fear is 
followed by trembling, pallor and chattering of the teeth."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), in fear there takes place a 
certain contraction from the outward to the inner parts of the body, the 
result being that the outer parts become cold; and for this reason 
trembling is occasioned in these parts, being caused by a lack of power 
in controlling the members: which lack of power is due to the want of 
heat, which is the instrument whereby the soul moves those members, as 
stated in De Anima ii, 4.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2

 Reply OBJ 1: When the heat withdraws from the outer to the inner parts, 
the inward heat increases, especially in the inferior or nutritive parts. 
Consequently the humid element being spent, thirst ensues; sometimes 
indeed the result is a loosening of the bowels, and urinary or even 
seminal evacuation. Or else such like evacuations are due to contraction 
of the abdomen and testicles, as the Philosopher says (De Problem. xxii, 
11).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2

 This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: In fear, heat abandons the heart, with a downward  
movement: hence in those who are afraid the heart especially trembles, as 
also those members which are connected with the breast where the heart 
resides. Hence those who fear tremble especially in their speech, on 
account of the tracheal artery being near the heart. The lower lip, too, 
and the lower jaw tremble, through their connection with the heart; which 
explains the chattering of the teeth. For the same reason the arms and 
hands tremble. Or else because the aforesaid members are more mobile. For 
which reason the knees tremble in those who are afraid, according to Is. 
35:3: "Strengthen ye the feeble hands, and confirm the trembling [Vulg.: 
'weak'] knees."


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether fear hinders action?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that fear hinders action. For action is hindered 
chiefly by a disturbance in the reason, which directs action. But fear 
disturbs reason, as stated above (A[2]). Therefore fear hinders action.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, those who fear while doing anything, are more apt to 
fail: thus a man who walks on a plank placed aloft, easily falls through 
fear; whereas, if he were to walk on the same plank down below, he would 
not fall, through not being afraid. Therefore fear hinders action.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, laziness or sloth is a kind of fear. But laziness 
hinders action. Therefore fear does too.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Apostle says (Phil. 2:12): "With fear and trembling 
work out your salvation": and he would not say this if fear were a 
hindrance to a good work. Therefore fear does not hinder a good action.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, Man's exterior actions are caused by the soul as first 
mover, but by the bodily members as instruments. Now action may be 
hindered both by defect of the instrument, and by defect of the principal 
mover. On the part of the bodily instruments, fear, considered in itself, 
is always apt to hinder exterior action, on account of the outward 
members being deprived, through fear, of their heat. But on the part of 
the soul, if the fear be moderate, without much disturbance of the 
reason, it conduces to working well, in so far as it causes a certain 
solicitude, and makes a man take counsel and work with greater attention. 
If, however, fear increases so much as to disturb the reason, it hinders 
action even on the part of the soul. But of such a fear the Apostle does 
not speak.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

 This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: He that falls from a plank placed aloft, suffers a 
disturbance of his imagination, through fear of the fall that is pictured 
to his imagination.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[44] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1 

 Reply OBJ 3: Everyone in fear shuns that which he fears: and therefore, 
since laziness is a fear of work itself as being toilsome, it hinders 
work by withdrawing the will from it. But fear of other things conduces 
to action, in so far as it inclines the will to do that whereby a man 
escapes from what he fears.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] Out. Para. 1/1

OF DARING (FOUR ARTICLES)

 We must now consider daring: under which head there are four points of 
inquiry:

 (1) Whether daring is contrary to fear?

 (2) How is daring related to hope?

 (3) Of the cause of daring;

 (4) Of its effect.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether daring is contrary to fear?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that daring is not contrary to fear. For Augustine 
says (QQ. 83, qu. 31) that "daring is a vice." Now vice is contrary to 
virtue. Since, therefore, fear is not a virtue but a passion, it seems 
that daring is not contrary to fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, to one thing there is one contrary. But hope is contrary 
to fear. Therefore daring is not contrary to fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, every passion excludes its opposite. But fear excludes 
safety; for Augustine says (Confess. ii, 6) that "fear takes forethought 
for safety." Therefore safety is contrary to fear. Therefore daring is 
not contrary to fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that "daring is 
contrary to fear."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It is of the essence of contraries to be "farthest 
removed from one another," as stated in Metaph. x, 4. Now that which is 
farthest removed from fear, is daring: since fear turns away from the 
future hurt, on account of its victory over him that fears it; whereas 
daring turns on threatened danger because of its own victory over that 
same danger. Consequently it is evident that daring is contrary to fear.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Anger, daring and all the names of the passions can be 
taken in two ways. First, as denoting absolutely movements of the 
sensitive appetite in respect of some object, good or bad: and thus they 
are names of passions. Secondly, as denoting besides this movement, a 
straying from the order of reason: and thus they are names of vices. It 
is in this sense that Augustine speaks of daring: but we are speaking of 
it in the first sense.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: To one thing, in the same respect, there are not several 
contraries; but in different respects nothing prevents one thing having 
several contraries. Accordingly it has been said above (Q[23], A[2]; 
Q[40], A[4]) that the irascible passions admit of a twofold  contrariety: 
one, according to the opposition of good and evil, and thus fear is 
contrary to hope: the other, according to the opposition of approach and 
withdrawal, and thus daring is contrary to fear, and despair contrary to 
hope.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Safety does not denote something contrary to fear, but 
merely the exclusion of fear: for he is said to be safe, who fears not. 
Wherefore safety is opposed to fear, as a privation: while daring is 
opposed thereto as a contrary. And as contrariety implies privation, so 
daring implies safety.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether daring ensues from hope?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that daring does not ensue from hope. Because 
daring regards evil and fearful things, as stated in Ethic. iii, 7. But 
hope regards good things, as stated above (Q[40], A[1]). Therefore they 
have different objects and are not in the same order. Therefore daring 
does not ensue from hope.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, just as daring is contrary to fear, so is despair 
contrary to hope. But fear does not ensue from despair: in fact, despair 
excludes fear, as the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5). Therefore daring 
does not result from hope.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, daring is intent on something good, viz. victory. But it 
belongs to hope to tend to that which is good and difficult. Therefore 
daring is the same as hope; and consequently does not result from it.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. iii, 8) that "those are 
hopeful are full of daring." Therefore it seems that daring ensues from 
hope.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, As we have often stated (Q[22], A[2]; Q[35], A[1]; Q[41], 
A[1]), all these passions belong to the appetitive power. Now every 
movement of the appetitive power is reducible to one either of pursuit or 
of avoidance. Again, pursuit or avoidance is of something either by 
reason of itself or by reason of something else. By reason of itself, 
good is the object of pursuit, and evil, the object of avoidance: but by 
reason of something else, evil can be the object of pursuit, through some 
good attaching to it; and good can be the object of avoidance, through 
some evil attaching to it. Now that which is by reason of something else, 
follows that which is by reason of itself. Consequently pursuit of evil 
follows pursuit of good; and avoidance of good follows avoidance of evil. 
Now these four things belong to four passions, since pursuit of good 
belongs to hope, avoidance of evil to fear, the pursuit of the fearful 
evil belongs to daring, and the avoidance of good to despair. It follows, 
therefore, that daring results from hope; since it is in the hope of 
overcoming the threatening object of fear, that one attacks it boldly. 
But despair results from fear: since the reason why a man despairs is 
because he fears the difficulty attaching to the good he should hope for. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: This argument would hold, if good and evil were not 
co-ordinate objects. But because evil has a certain relation to good, 
since it comes after good, as privation comes after habit; consequently 
daring which pursues evil, comes after hope which pursues good.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Although good, absolutely speaking, is prior to evil, yet 
avoidance of evil precedes avoidance of good; just as the pursuit of good 
precedes the pursuit of evil. Consequently just as hope precedes daring, 
so fear precedes despair. And just as fear does not always lead to 
despair, but only when it is intense; so hope does not always lead to 
daring, save only when it is strong.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Although the object of daring is an evil to which, in the 
estimation of the daring man, the good of victory is conjoined; yet 
daring regards the evil, and hope regards the conjoined good. In like 
manner despair regards directly the good which it turns away from, while 
fear regards the conjoined evil. Hence, properly speaking, daring is not 
a part of hope, but its effect: just as despair is an effect, not a part, 
of fear. For this reason, too, daring cannot be a principal passion.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether some defect is a cause of daring?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that some defect is a cause of daring. For the 
Philosopher says (De Problem. xxvii, 4) that "lovers of wine are strong 
and daring." But from wine ensues the effect of drunkenness. Therefore 
daring is caused by a defect.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that "those who have 
no experience of danger are bold." But want of experience is a defect. 
Therefore daring is caused by a defect.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, those who have suffered wrongs are wont to be daring; 
"like the beasts when beaten," as stated in Ethic. iii, 5. But the 
suffering of wrongs pertains to defect. Therefore daring is caused by a 
defect.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that the cause of 
daring "is the presence in the imagination of the hope that the means of 
safety are nigh, and that the things to be feared are either non-existent 
or far off." But anything pertaining to defect implies either the removal 
of the means of safety, or the proximity of something to be feared. 
Therefore nothing pertaining to defect is a cause of daring.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, As stated above (AA[1],2) daring results from hope and is 
contrary to fear: wherefore whatever is naturally apt to cause hope or 
banish fear, is a cause of daring. Since, however, fear and hope, and 
also daring, being passions, consist in a movement of the appetite, and 
in a certain bodily transmutation; a thing may be considered as the cause 
of daring in two ways, whether  by raising hope, or by banishing fear; in 
one way, in the part of the appetitive movement; in another way, on the 
part of the bodily transmutation.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

 On the part of the appetitive movement which follows apprehension, hope 
that leads to daring is roused by those things that make us reckon 
victory as possible. Such things regard either our own power, as bodily 
strength, experience of dangers, abundance of wealth, and the like; or 
they regard the powers of others, such as having a great number of 
friends or any other means of help, especially if a man trust in the 
Divine assistance: wherefore "those are more daring, with whom it is well 
in regard to godlike things," as the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5). Fear 
is banished, in this way, by the removal of threatening causes of fear; 
for instance, by the fact that a man has not enemies, through having 
harmed nobody, so that he is not aware of any imminent danger; since 
those especially appear to be threatened by danger, who have harmed 
others.

 On the part of the bodily transmutation, daring is caused through the 
incitement of hope and the banishment of fear, by those things which 
raise the temperature about the heart. Wherefore the Philosopher says (De 
Part. Animal. iii, 4) that "those whose heart is small in size, are more 
daring; while animals whose heart is large are timid; because the natural 
heat is unable to give the same degree of temperature to a large as to a 
small heart; just as a fire does not heat a large house as well as it 
does a small house." He says also (De Problem. xxvii, 4), that "those 
whose lungs contain much blood, are more daring, through the heat in the 
heart that results therefrom." He says also in the same passage that 
"lovers of wine are more daring, on account of the heat of the wine": 
hence it has been said above (Q[40], A[6]) that drunkenness conduces to 
hope, since the heat in the heart banishes fear and raises hope, by 
reason of the dilatation and enlargement of the heart.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Drunkenness causes daring, not through being a defect, but 
through dilating the heart: and again through making a man think greatly 
of himself.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Those who have no experience of dangers are more daring, 
not on account of a defect, but accidentally, i.e. in so far as through 
being inexperienced they do not know their own failings, nor the dangers 
that threaten. Hence it is that the removal of the cause of fear gives 
rise to daring.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2

 Reply OBJ 3: As the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) "those who have been 
wronged are courageous, because they think that God comes to the 
assistance of those who suffer unjustly."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2

 Hence it is evident that no defect causes daring except accidentally, 
i.e. in so far as some excellence attaches thereto, real or imaginary, 
either in oneself or in another.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1 

Whether the brave are more eager at first than in the midst of danger?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that the daring are not more eager at first than in 
the midst of danger. Because trembling is caused by fear, which is 
contrary to daring, as stated above (A[1]; Q[44], A[3]). But the daring 
sometimes tremble at first, as the Philosopher says (De Problem. xxvii, 
3). Therefore they are not more eager at first than in the midst of 
danger.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, passion is intensified by an increase in its object: 
thus since a good is lovable, what is better is yet more lovable. But the 
object of daring is something difficult. Therefore the greater the 
difficulty, the greater the daring. But danger is more arduous and 
difficult when present. It is then therefore that daring is greatest.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, anger is provoked by the infliction of wounds. But anger 
causes daring; for the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 5) that "anger makes 
man bold." Therefore when man is in the midst of danger and when he is 
being beaten, then is he most daring.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is said in Ethic. iii, 7 that "the daring are 
precipitate and full of eagerness before the danger, yet in the midst of 
dangers they stand aloof."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, Daring, being a movement of the sensitive appetite, 
follows an apprehension of the sensitive faculty. But the sensitive 
faculty cannot make comparisons, nor can it inquire into circumstances; 
its judgment is instantaneous. Now it happens sometimes that it is 
impossible for a man to take note in an instant of all the difficulties 
of a certain situation: hence there arises the movement of daring to face 
the danger; so that when he comes to experience the danger, he feels the 
difficulty to be greater than he expected, and so gives way.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

 On the other hand, reason discusses all the difficulties of a situation. 
Consequently men of fortitude who face danger according to the judgment 
of reason, at first seem slack, because they face the danger not from 
passion but with due deliberation. Yet when they are in the midst of 
danger, they experience nothing unforeseen, but sometimes the difficulty 
turns out to be less than they anticipated; wherefore they are more 
persevering. Moreover, it may be because they face the danger on account 
of the good of virtue which is the abiding object of their will, however 
great the danger may prove: whereas men of daring face the danger on 
account of a mere thought giving rise to hope and banishing fear, as 
stated above (A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Trembling does occur in men of daring, on account of the 
heat being withdrawn from the outer to the inner parts of the body, as 
occurs also in those who are afraid. But in men of daring the heat 
withdraws to the heart; whereas in those who are afraid, it withdraws to 
the inferior parts. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The object of love is good simply, wherefore if it be 
increased, love is increased simply. But the object of daring is a 
compound of good and evil; and the movement of daring towards evil 
presupposes the movement of hope towards good. If, therefore, so much 
difficulty be added to the danger that it overcomes hope, the movement of 
daring does not ensue, but fails. But if the movement of daring does 
ensue, the greater the danger, the greater is the daring considered to be.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[45] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Hurt does not give rise to anger unless there be some kind 
of hope, as we shall see later on (Q[46], A[1]). Consequently if the 
danger be so great as to banish all hope of victory, anger does not 
ensue. It is true, however, that if anger does ensue, there will be 
greater daring.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] Out. Para. 1/2

OF ANGER, IN ITSELF (EIGHT ARTICLES)

 We must now consider anger: and (1) anger in itself; (2) the cause of 
anger and its remedy; (3) the effect of anger.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] Out. Para. 2/2

 Under the first head there are eight points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether anger is a special passion?

 (2) Whether the object of anger is good or evil?

 (3) Whether anger is in the concupiscible faculty?

 (4) Whether anger is accompanied by an act of reason?

 (5) Whether anger is more natural than desire?

 (6) Whether anger is more grievous than hatred?

 (7) Whether anger is only towards those with whom we have a relation of 
justice?

 (8) Of the species of anger.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether anger is a special passion?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that anger is not a special passion. For the 
irascible power takes its name from anger [ira]. But there are several 
passions in this power, not only one. Therefore anger is not one special 
passion.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, to every special passion there is a contrary passion; as 
is evident by going through them one by one. But no passion is contrary 
to anger, as stated above (Q[23], A[3]). Therefore anger is not a special 
passion.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, one special passion does not include another. But anger 
includes several passions: since it accompanies sorrow, pleasure, and 
hope, as the Philosopher states (Rhet. ii, 2). Therefore anger is not a 
special passion.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 16) calls anger a special 
passion: and so does Cicero (De Quaest. Tusc. iv, 7).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, A thing is said to be general in two ways.  First, by 
predication; thus "animal" is general in respect of all animals. 
Secondly, by causality; thus the sun is the general cause of all things 
generated here below, according to Dionysius (Div. Nom. iv). Because just 
as a genus contains potentially many differences, according to a likeness 
of matter; so an efficient cause contains many effects according to its 
active power. Now it happens that an effect is produced by the 
concurrence of various causes; and since every cause remains somewhat in 
its effect, we may say that, in yet a third way, an effect which is due 
to the concurrence of several causes, has a certain generality, inasmuch 
as several causes are, in a fashion, actually existing therein.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] Body Para. 2/2

 Accordingly in the first way, anger is not a general passion but is 
condivided with the other passions, as stated above (Q[23], A[4]). In 
like manner, neither is it in the second way: since it is not a cause of 
the other passions. But in this way, love may be called a general 
passion, as Augustine declares (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7,9), because love is 
the primary root of all the other passions, as stated above (Q[27], A[4]
). But, in a third way, anger may be called a general passion, inasmuch 
as it is caused by a concurrence of several passions. Because the 
movement of anger does not arise save on account of some pain inflicted, 
and unless there be desire and hope of revenge: for, as the Philosopher 
says (Rhet. ii, 2), "the angry man hopes to punish; since he craves for 
revenge as being possible." Consequently if the person, who inflicted the 
injury, excel very much, anger does not ensue, but only sorrow, as 
Avicenna states (De Anima iv, 6).

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The irascible power takes its name from "ira" [anger], not 
because every movement of that power is one of anger; but because all its 
movements terminate in anger; and because, of all these movements, anger 
is the most patent.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: From the very fact that anger is caused by contrary 
passions, i.e. by hope, which is of good, and by sorrow, which is of 
evil, it includes in itself contrariety: and consequently it has no 
contrary outside itself. Thus also in mixed colors there is no 
contrariety, except that of the simple colors from which they are made.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Anger includes several passions, not indeed as a genus 
includes several species; but rather according to the inclusion of cause 
and effect.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the object of anger is good or evil?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that the object of anger is evil. For Gregory of 
Nyssa says [*Nemesius, De Nat. Hom. xxi.] that anger is "the sword-bearer 
of desire," inasmuch, to wit, as it assails whatever obstacle stands in 
the way of desire. But an obstacle has the character of evil. Therefore 
anger regards evil as its object.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, anger and hatred agree in their effect, since  each 
seeks to inflict harm on another. But hatred regards evil as its object, 
as stated above (Q[29], A[1]). Therefore anger does also.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, anger arises from sorrow; wherefore the Philosopher says 
(Ethic. viii, 6) that "anger acts with sorrow." But evil is the object of 
sorrow. Therefore it is also the object of anger.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2

 On the contrary, Augustine says (Confess. ii, 6) that "anger craves for 
revenge." But the desire for revenge is a desire for something good: 
since revenge belongs to justice. Therefore the object of anger is good.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2

 Moreover, anger is always accompanied by hope, wherefore it causes 
pleasure, as the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 2). But the object of hope 
and of pleasure is good. Therefore good is also the object of anger.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, The movement of the appetitive power follows an act of 
the apprehensive power. Now the apprehensive power apprehends a thing in 
two ways. First, by way of an incomplex object, as when we understand 
what a man is; secondly, by way of a complex object, as when we 
understand that whiteness is in a man. Consequently in each of these ways 
the appetitive power can tend to both good and evil: by way of a simple 
and incomplex object, when the appetite simply follows and adheres to 
good, or recoils from evil: and such movements are desire, hope, 
pleasure, sorrow, and so forth: by way of a complex object, as when the 
appetite is concerned with some good or evil being in, or being done to, 
another, either seeking this or recoiling from it. This is evident in the 
case of love and hatred: for we love someone, in so far as we wish some 
good to be in him; and we hate someone, in so far as we wish some evil to 
be in him. It is the same with anger; for when a man is angry, he wishes 
to be avenged on someone. Hence the movement of anger has a twofold 
tendency: viz. to vengeance itself, which it desires and hopes for as 
being a good, wherefore it takes pleasure in it; and to the person on 
whom it seeks vengeance, as to something contrary and hurtful, which 
bears the character of evil.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Body Para. 2/3

 We must, however, observe a twofold difference in this respect, between 
anger on the one side, and hatred and love on the other. The first 
difference is that anger always regards two objects: whereas love and 
hatred sometimes regard but one object, as when a man is said to love 
wine or something of the kind, or to hate it. The second difference is, 
that both the objects of love are good: since the lover wishes good to 
someone, as to something agreeable to himself: while both the objects of 
hatred bear the character of evil: for the man who hates, wishes evil to 
someone, as to something disagreeable to him. Whereas anger regards one 
object under the aspect of evil, viz. the noxious person, on whom it 
seeks to be avenged. Consequently it is a passion somewhat made up of 
contrary passions.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[46] A[2] Body Para. 3/3

 This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.