Aquin.: SMT FS Prologue Para. 1/1

FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (FS) (QQ[1]-114)


TREATISE ON THE LAST END (QQ[1]-5)


PROLOGUE

 Since, as Damascene states (De Fide Orth. ii, 12), man is said to be 
made in God's image, in so far as the image implies "an intelligent being 
endowed with free-will and self-movement": now that we have treated of 
the exemplar, i.e. God, and of those things which came forth from the 
power of God in accordance with His will; it remains for us to treat of 
His image, i.e. man, inasmuch as he too is the principle of his actions, 
as having free-will and control of his actions.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] Out. Para. 1/2

OF MAN'S LAST END (EIGHT ARTICLES)

 In this matter we shall consider first the last end of human life; and 
secondly, those things by means of which man may advance towards this 
end, or stray from the path: for the end is the rule of whatever is 
ordained to the end. And since the last end of human life is stated to be 
happiness, we must consider (1) the last end in general; (2) happiness.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] Out. Para. 2/2

 Under the first head there are eight points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether it belongs to man to act for an end?

 (2) Whether this is proper to the rational nature?

 (3) Whether a man's actions are specified by their end?

 (4) Whether there is any last end of human life?

 (5) Whether one man can have several last ends?

 (6) Whether man ordains all to the last end?

 (7) Whether all men have the same last end?

 (8) Whether all other creatures concur with man in that last end?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether it belongs to man to act for an end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that it does not belong to man to act for an end. 
For a cause is naturally first. But an end, in its very name, implies 
something that is last. Therefore an end is not a cause. But that for 
which a man acts, is the cause of his action; since this preposition 
"for" indicates a relation of causality. Therefore it does not belong to 
man to act for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, that which is itself the last end is not for an end. But 
in some cases the last end is an action, as the Philosopher states 
(Ethic. i, 1). Therefore man does not do everything for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, then does a man seem to act for an end, when he acts 
deliberately. But man does many things without deliberation, sometimes 
not even thinking of what he is doing; for instance when one moves one's 
foot or hand, or scratches one's  beard, while intent on something else. 
Therefore man does not do everything for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, All things contained in a genus are derived from the 
principle of that genus. Now the end is the principle in human 
operations, as the Philosopher states (Phys. ii, 9). Therefore it belongs 
to man to do everything for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Of actions done by man those alone are properly called 
"human," which are proper to man as man. Now man differs from irrational 
animals in this, that he is master of his actions. Wherefore those 
actions alone are properly called human, of which man is master. Now man 
is master of his actions through his reason and will; whence, too, the 
free-will is defined as "the faculty and will of reason." Therefore those 
actions are properly called human which proceed from a deliberate will. 
And if any other actions are found in man, they can be called actions "of 
a man," but not properly "human" actions, since they are not proper to 
man as man. Now it is clear that whatever actions proceed from a power, 
are caused by that power in accordance with the nature of its object. But 
the object of the will is the end and the good. Therefore all human 
actions must be for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Although the end be last in the order of execution, yet it 
is first in the order of the agent's intention. And it is this way that 
it is a cause.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: If any human action be the last end, it must be voluntary, 
else it would not be human, as stated above. Now an action is voluntary 
in one of two ways: first, because it is commanded by the will, e.g. to 
walk, or to speak; secondly, because it is elicited by the will, for 
instance the very act of willing. Now it is impossible for the very act 
elicited by the will to be the last end. For the object of the will is 
the end, just as the object of sight is color: wherefore just as the 
first visible cannot be the act of seeing, because every act of seeing is 
directed to a visible object; so the first appetible, i.e. the end, 
cannot be the very act of willing. Consequently it follows that if a 
human action be the last end, it must be an action commanded by the will: 
so that there, some action of man, at least the act of willing, is for 
the end. Therefore whatever a man does, it is true to say that man acts 
for an end, even when he does that action in which the last end consists.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Such like actions are not properly human actions; since 
they do not proceed from deliberation of the reason, which is the proper 
principle of human actions. Therefore they have indeed an imaginary end, 
but not one that is fixed by reason.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether it is proper to the rational nature to act for an end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that it is proper to the rational nature to act for 
an end. For man, to whom it belongs to act for an end,  never acts for an 
unknown end. On the other hand, there are many things that have no 
knowledge of an end; either because they are altogether without 
knowledge, as insensible creatures: or because they do not apprehend the 
idea of an end as such, as irrational animals. Therefore it seems proper 
to the rational nature to act for an end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, to act for an end is to order one's action to an end. 
But this is the work of reason. Therefore it does not belong to things 
that lack reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, the good and the end is the object of the will. But "the 
will is in the reason" (De Anima iii, 9). Therefore to act for an end 
belongs to none but a rational nature.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher proves (Phys. ii, 5) that "not only 
mind but also nature acts for an end."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, Every agent, of necessity, acts for an end. For if, in a 
number of causes ordained to one another, the first be removed, the 
others must, of necessity, be removed also. Now the first of all causes 
is the final cause. The reason of which is that matter does not receive 
form, save in so far as it is moved by an agent; for nothing reduces 
itself from potentiality to act. But an agent does not move except out of 
intention for an end. For if the agent were not determinate to some 
particular effect, it would not do one thing rather than another: 
consequently in order that it produce a determinate effect, it must, of 
necessity, be determined to some certain one, which has the nature of an 
end. And just as this determination is effected, in the rational nature, 
by the "rational appetite," which is called the will; so, in other 
things, it is caused by their natural inclination, which is called the 
"natural appetite."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] Body Para. 2/2

 Nevertheless it must be observed that a thing tends to an end, by its 
action or movement, in two ways: first, as a thing, moving itself to the 
end, as man; secondly, as a thing moved by another to the end, as an 
arrow tends to a determinate end through being moved by the archer who 
directs his action to the end. Therefore those things that are possessed 
of reason, move themselves to an end; because they have dominion over 
their actions through their free-will, which is the "faculty of will and 
reason." But those things that lack reason tend to an end, by natural 
inclination, as being moved by another and not by themselves; since they 
do not know the nature of an end as such, and consequently cannot ordain 
anything to an end, but can be ordained to an end only by another. For 
the entire irrational nature is in comparison to God as an instrument to 
the principal agent, as stated above (FP, Q[22], A[2], ad 4; FP, Q[103], 
A[1], ad 3). Consequently it is proper to the rational nature to tend to 
an end, as directing [agens] and leading itself to the end: whereas it is 
proper to the irrational nature to tend to an end, as directed or led by 
another, whether it apprehend the end, as do irrational animals, or do 
not apprehend it, as is the case of those things which are altogether 
void of knowledge. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: When a man of himself acts for an end, he knows the end: 
but when he is directed or led by another, for instance, when he acts at 
another's command, or when he is moved under another's compulsion, it is 
not necessary that he should know the end. And it is thus with irrational 
creatures.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: To ordain towards an end belongs to that which directs 
itself to an end: whereas to be ordained to an end belongs to that which 
is directed by another to an end. And this can belong to an irrational 
nature, but owing to some one possessed of reason.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The object of the will is the end and the good in 
universal. Consequently there can be no will in those things that lack 
reason and intellect, since they cannot apprehend the universal; but they 
have a natural appetite or a sensitive appetite, determinate to some 
particular good. Now it is clear that particular causes are moved by a 
universal cause: thus the governor of a city, who intends the common 
good, moves, by his command, all the particular departments of the city. 
Consequently all things that lack reason are, of necessity, moved to 
their particular ends by some rational will which extends to the 
universal good, namely by the Divine will.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether human acts are specified by their end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that human acts are not specified by their end. For 
the end is an extrinsic cause. But everything is specified by an 
intrinsic principle. Therefore human acts are not specified by their end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, that which gives a thing its species should exist before 
it. But the end comes into existence afterwards. Therefore a human act 
does not derive its species from the end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, one thing cannot be in more than one species. But one 
and the same act may happen to be ordained to various ends. Therefore the 
end does not give the species to human acts.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Mor. Eccl. et Manich. ii, 13): 
"According as their end is worthy of blame or praise so are our deeds 
worthy of blame or praise."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that Each thing receives its species in respect of an act and 
not in respect of potentiality; wherefore things composed of matter and 
form are established in their respective species by their own forms. And 
this is also to be observed in proper movements. For since movements are, 
in a way, divided into action and passion, each of these receives its 
species from an act; action indeed from the act which is the principle of 
acting, and passion from the act which is the terminus of the movement. 
Wherefore heating, as an action, is nothing else than a certain movement 
proceeding from heat, while heating as a passion is nothing else  than a 
movement towards heat: and it is the definition that shows the specific 
nature. And either way, human acts, whether they be considered as 
actions, or as passions, receive their species from the end. For human 
acts can be considered in both ways, since man moves himself, and is 
moved by himself. Now it has been stated above (A[1]) that acts are 
called human, inasmuch as they proceed from a deliberate will. Now the 
object of the will is the good and the end. And hence it is clear that 
the principle of human acts, in so far as they are human, is the end. In 
like manner it is their terminus: for the human act terminates at that 
which the will intends as the end; thus in natural agents the form of the 
thing generated is conformed to the form of the generator. And since, as 
Ambrose says (Prolog. super Luc.) "morality is said properly of man," 
moral acts properly speaking receive their species from the end, for 
moral acts are the same as human acts.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The end is not altogether extrinsic to the act, because it 
is related to the act as principle or terminus; and thus it just this 
that is essential to an act, viz. to proceed from something, considered 
as action, and to proceed towards something, considered as passion.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The end, in so far as it pre-exists in the intention, 
pertains to the will, as stated above (A[1], ad 1). And it is thus that 
it gives the species to the human or moral act.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: One and the same act, in so far as it proceeds once from 
the agent, is ordained to but one proximate end, from which it has its 
species: but it can be ordained to several remote ends, of which one is 
the end of the other. It is possible, however, that an act which is one 
in respect of its natural species, be ordained to several ends of the 
will: thus this act "to kill a man," which is but one act in respect of 
its natural species, can be ordained, as to an end, to the safeguarding 
of justice, and to the satisfying of anger: the result being that there 
would be several acts in different species of morality: since in one way 
there will be an act of virtue, in another, an act of vice. For a 
movement does not receive its species from that which is its terminus 
accidentally, but only from that which is its "per se" terminus. Now 
moral ends are accidental to a natural thing, and conversely the relation 
to a natural end is accidental to morality. Consequently there is no 
reason why acts which are the same considered in their natural species, 
should not be diverse, considered in their moral species, and conversely.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether there is one last end of human life?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that there is no last end of human life, but that 
we proceed to infinity. For good is essentially diffusive, as Dionysius 
states (Div. Nom. iv). Consequently if that which proceeds from good is 
itself good, the latter must needs diffuse some other good: so that the 
diffusion of good goes on indefinitely. But good has the nature of an 
end. Therefore there is  an indefinite series of ends.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, things pertaining to the reason can be multiplied to 
infinity: thus mathematical quantities have no limit. For the same reason 
the species of numbers are infinite, since, given any number, the reason 
can think of one yet greater. But desire of the end is consequent on the 
apprehension of the reason. Therefore it seems that there is also an 
infinite series of ends.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, the good and the end is the object of the will. But the 
will can react on itself an infinite number of times: for I can will 
something, and will to will it, and so on indefinitely. Therefore there 
is an infinite series of ends of the human will, and there is no last end 
of the human will.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Metaph. ii, 2) that "to suppose a 
thing to be indefinite is to deny that it is good." But the good is that 
which has the nature of an end. Therefore it is contrary to the nature of 
an end to proceed indefinitely. Therefore it is necessary to fix one last 
end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, Absolutely speaking, it is not possible to proceed 
indefinitely in the matter of ends, from any point of view. For in 
whatsoever things there is an essential order of one to another, if the 
first be removed, those that are ordained to the first, must of necessity 
be removed also. Wherefore the Philosopher proves (Phys. viii, 5) that we 
cannot proceed to infinitude in causes of movement, because then there 
would be no first mover, without which neither can the others move, since 
they move only through being moved by the first mover. Now there is to be 
observed a twofold order in ends---the order of intention and the order 
of execution: and in either of these orders there must be something 
first. For that which is first in the order of intention, is the 
principle, as it were, moving the appetite; consequently, if you remove 
this principle, there will be nothing to move the appetite. On the other 
hand, the principle in execution is that wherein operation has its 
beginning; and if this principle be taken away, no one will begin to 
work. Now the principle in the intention is the last end; while the 
principle in execution is the first of the things which are ordained to 
the end. Consequently, on neither side is it possible to go to infinity 
since if there were no last end, nothing would be desired, nor would any 
action have its term, nor would the intention of the agent be at rest; 
while if there is no first thing among those that are ordained to the 
end, none would begin to work at anything, and counsel would have no 
term, but would continue indefinitely.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] Body Para. 2/2

 On the other hand, nothing hinders infinity from being in things that 
are ordained to one another not essentially but accidentally; for 
accidental causes are indeterminate. And in this way it happens that 
there is an accidental infinity of ends, and of things ordained to the 
end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The very nature of good is that something flows  from it, 
but not that it flows from something else. Since, therefore, good has the 
nature of end, and the first good is the last end, this argument does not 
prove that there is no last end; but that from the end, already supposed, 
we may proceed downwards indefinitely towards those things that are 
ordained to the end. And this would be true if we considered but the 
power of the First Good, which is infinite. But, since the First Good 
diffuses itself according to the intellect, to which it is proper to flow 
forth into its effects according to a certain fixed form; it follows that 
there is a certain measure to the flow of good things from the First Good 
from Which all other goods share the power of diffusion. Consequently the 
diffusion of goods does not proceed indefinitely but, as it is written 
(Wis. 11:21), God disposes all things "in number, weight and measure."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: In things which are of themselves, reason begins from 
principles that are known naturally, and advances to some term. Wherefore 
the Philosopher proves (Poster. i, 3) that there is no infinite process 
in demonstrations, because there we find a process of things having an 
essential, not an accidental, connection with one another. But in those 
things which are accidentally connected, nothing hinders the reason from 
proceeding indefinitely. Now it is accidental to a stated quantity or 
number, as such, that quantity or unity be added to it. Wherefore in such 
like things nothing hinders the reason from an indefinite process.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: This multiplication of acts of the will reacting on itself, 
is accidental to the order of ends. This is clear from the fact that in 
regard to one and the same end, the will reacts on itself indifferently 
once or several times.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether one man can have several last ends?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem possible for one man's will to be directed at the 
same time to several things, as last ends. For Augustine says (De Civ. 
Dei xix, 1) that some held man's last end to consist in four things, viz. 
"in pleasure, repose, the gifts of nature, and virtue." But these are 
clearly more than one thing. Therefore one man can place the last end of 
his will in many things.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, things not in opposition to one another do not exclude 
one another. Now there are many things which are not in opposition to one 
another. Therefore the supposition that one thing is the last end of the 
will does not exclude others.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, by the fact that it places its last end in one thing, 
the will does not lose its freedom. But before it placed its last end in 
that thing, e.g. pleasure, it could place it in something else, e.g. 
riches. Therefore even after having placed his last end in pleasure, a 
man can at the same time place his last end in riches. Therefore it is 
possible for one man's will to be directed at the same time to several 
things, as last ends. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, That in which a man rests as in his last end, is master 
of his affections, since he takes therefrom his entire rule of life. 
Hence of gluttons it is written (Phil. 3:19): "Whose god is their belly": 
viz. because they place their last end in the pleasures of the belly. Now 
according to Mt. 6:24, "No man can serve two masters," such, namely, as 
are not ordained to one another. Therefore it is impossible for one man 
to have several last ends not ordained to one another.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, It is impossible for one man's will to be directed at the 
same time to diverse things, as last ends. Three reasons may be assigned 
for this. First, because, since everything desires its own perfection, a 
man desires for his ultimate end, that which he desires as his perfect 
and crowning good. Hence Augustine (De Civ. Dei xix, 1): "In speaking of 
the end of good we mean now, not that it passes away so as to be no more, 
but that it is perfected so as to be complete." It is therefore necessary 
for the last end so to fill man's appetite, that nothing is left besides 
it for man to desire. Which is not possible, if something else be 
required for his perfection. Consequently it is not possible for the 
appetite so to tend to two things, as though each were its perfect good.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Body Para. 2/3

 The second reason is because, just as in the process of reasoning, the 
principle is that which is naturally known, so in the process of the 
rational appetite, i.e. the will, the principle needs to be that which is 
naturally desired. Now this must needs be one: since nature tends to one 
thing only. But the principle in the process of the rational appetite is 
the last end. Therefore that to which the will tends, as to its last end, 
is one.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] Body Para. 3/3

 The third reason is because, since voluntary actions receive their 
species from the end, as stated above (A[3]), they must needs receive 
their genus from the last end, which is common to them all: just as 
natural things are placed in a genus according to a common form. Since, 
then, all things that can be desired by the will, belong, as such, to one 
genus, the last end must needs be one. And all the more because in every 
genus there is one first principle; and the last end has the nature of a 
first principle, as stated above. Now as the last end of man, simply as 
man, is to the whole human race, so is the last end of any individual man 
to that individual. Therefore, just as of all men there is naturally one 
last end, so the will of an individual man must be fixed on one last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: All these several objects were considered as one perfect 
good resulting therefrom, by those who placed in them the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Although it is possible to find several things which are 
not in opposition to one another, yet it is contrary to a thing's perfect 
good, that anything besides be required for that thing's perfection. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The power of the will does not extend to making opposites 
exist at the same time. Which would be the case were it to tend to 
several diverse objects as last ends, as has been shown above (ad 2).


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether man will all, whatsoever he wills, for the last end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that man does not will all, whatsoever he wills, 
for the last end. For things ordained to the last end are said to be 
serious matter, as being useful. But jests are foreign to serious matter. 
Therefore what man does in jest, he ordains not to the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says at the beginning of his Metaphysics 
1,[2] that speculative science is sought for its own sake. Now it cannot 
be said that each speculative science is the last end. Therefore man does 
not desire all, whatsoever he desires, for the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, whosoever ordains something to an end, thinks of that 
end. But man does not always think of the last end in all that he desires 
or does. Therefore man neither desires nor does all for the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xix, 1): "That is the end 
of our good, for the sake of which we love other things, whereas we love 
it for its own sake."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Man must, of necessity, desire all, whatsoever he 
desires, for the last end. This is evident for two reasons. First, 
because whatever man desires, he desires it under the aspect of good. And 
if he desire it, not as his perfect good, which is the last end, he must, 
of necessity, desire it as tending to the perfect good, because the 
beginning of anything is always ordained to its completion; as is clearly 
the case in effects both of nature and of art. Wherefore every beginning 
of perfection is ordained to complete perfection which is achieved 
through the last end. Secondly, because the last end stands in the same 
relation in moving the appetite, as the first mover in other movements. 
Now it is clear that secondary moving causes do not move save inasmuch as 
they are moved by the first mover. Therefore secondary objects of the 
appetite do not move the appetite, except as ordained to the first object 
of the appetite, which is the last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Actions done jestingly are not directed to any external 
end; but merely to the good of the jester, in so far as they afford him 
pleasure or relaxation. But man's consummate good is his last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The same applies to speculative science; which is desired 
as the scientist's good, included in complete and perfect good, which is 
the ultimate end. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: One need not always be thinking of the last end, whenever 
one desires or does something: but the virtue of the first intention, 
which was in respect of the last end, remains in every desire directed to 
any object whatever, even though one's thoughts be not actually directed 
to the last end. Thus while walking along the road one needs not to be 
thinking of the end at every step.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether all men have the same last end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that all men have not the same last end. For before 
all else the unchangeable good seems to be the last end of man. But some 
turn away from the unchangeable good, by sinning. Therefore all men have 
not the same last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, man's entire life is ruled according to his last end. 
If, therefore, all men had the same last end, they would not have various 
pursuits in life. Which is evidently false.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, the end is the term of action. But actions are of 
individuals. Now although men agree in their specific nature, yet they 
differ in things pertaining to individuals. Therefore all men have not 
the same last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. xiii, 3) that all men agree in 
desiring the last end, which is happiness.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, We can speak of the last end in two ways: first, 
considering only the aspect of last end; secondly, considering the thing 
in which the aspect of last end is realized. So, then, as to the aspect 
of last end, all agree in desiring the last end: since all desire the 
fulfilment of their perfection, and it is precisely this fulfilment in 
which the last end consists, as stated above (A[5]). But as to the thing 
in which this aspect is realized, all men are not agreed as to their last 
end: since some desire riches as their consummate good; some, pleasure; 
others, something else. Thus to every taste the sweet is pleasant but to 
some, the sweetness of wine is most pleasant, to others, the sweetness of 
honey, or of something similar. Yet that sweet is absolutely the best of 
all pleasant things, in which he who has the best taste takes most 
pleasure. In like manner that good is most complete which the man with 
well disposed affections desires for his last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Those who sin turn from that in which their last end really 
consists: but they do not turn away from the intention of the last end, 
which intention they mistakenly seek in other things.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Various pursuits in life are found among men by reason of 
the various things in which men seek to find their last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1 

 Reply OBJ 3: Although actions are of individuals, yet their first 
principle of action is nature, which tends to one thing, as stated above 
(A[5]).


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether other creatures concur in that last end?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that all other creatures concur in man's last end. 
For the end corresponds to the beginning. But man's beginning---i.e. 
God---is also the beginning of all else. Therefore all other things 
concur in man's last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "God turns all things 
to Himself as to their last end." But He is also man's last end; because 
He alone is to be enjoyed by man, as Augustine says (De Doctr. Christ. i, 
5,22). Therefore other things, too, concur in man's last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, man's last end is the object of the will. But the object 
of the will is the universal good, which is the end of all. Therefore 
other things, too, concur in man's last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, man's last end is happiness; which all men desire, as 
Augustine says (De Trin. xiii, 3,4). But "happiness is not possible for 
animals bereft of reason," as Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 5). Therefore 
other things do not concur in man's last end.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, As the Philosopher says (Phys. ii, 2), the end is 
twofold---the end "for which" and the end "by which"; viz. the thing 
itself in which is found the aspect of good, and the use or acquisition 
of that thing. Thus we say that the end of the movement of a weighty body 
is either a lower place as "thing," or to be in a lower place, as "use"; 
and the end of the miser is money as "thing," or possession of money as 
"use."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Body Para. 2/3

 If, therefore, we speak of man's last end as of the thing which is the 
end, thus all other things concur in man's last end, since God is the 
last end of man and of all other things. If, however, we speak of man's 
last end, as of the acquisition of the end, then irrational creatures do 
not concur with man in this end. For man and other rational creatures 
attain to their last end by knowing and loving God: this is not possible 
to other creatures, which acquire their last end, in so far as they share 
in the Divine likeness, inasmuch as they are, or live, or even know.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[1] A[8] Body Para. 3/3

 Hence it is evident how the objections are solved: since happiness means 
the acquisition of the last end.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] Out. Para. 1/2

OF THOSE THINGS IN WHICH MAN'S HAPPINESS CONSISTS (EIGHT ARTICLES)

 We have now to consider happiness: and (1) in what it consists; (2) what 
it is; (3) how we can obtain it.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] Out. Para. 2/2

 Concerning the first there are eight points of inquiry: 

 (1) Whether happiness consists in wealth?

 (2) Whether in honor?

 (3) Whether in fame or glory?

 (4) Whether in power?

 (5) Whether in any good of the body?

 (6) Whether in pleasure?

 (7) Whether in any good of the soul?

 (8) Whether in any created good?


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether man's happiness consists in wealth?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that man's happiness consists in wealth. For since 
happiness is man's last end, it must consist in that which has the 
greatest hold on man's affections. Now this is wealth: for it is written 
(Eccles. 10:19): "All things obey money." Therefore man's happiness 
consists in wealth.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, according to Boethius (De Consol. iii), happiness is "a 
state of life made perfect by the aggregate of all good things." Now 
money seems to be the means of possessing all things: for, as the 
Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 5), money was invented, that it might be a 
sort of guarantee for the acquisition of whatever man desires. Therefore 
happiness consists in wealth.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, since the desire for the sovereign good never fails, it 
seems to be infinite. But this is the case with riches more than anything 
else; since "a covetous man shall not be satisfied with riches" (Eccles. 
5:9). Therefore happiness consists in wealth.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Man's good consists in retaining happiness rather than 
in spreading it. But as Boethius says (De Consol. ii), "wealth shines in 
giving rather than in hoarding: for the miser is hateful, whereas the 
generous man is applauded." Therefore man's happiness does not consist in 
wealth.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, It is impossible for man's happiness to consist in 
wealth. For wealth is twofold, as the Philosopher says (Polit. i, 3), 
viz. natural and artificial. Natural wealth is that which serves man as a 
remedy for his natural wants: such as food, drink, clothing, cars, 
dwellings, and such like, while artificial wealth is that which is not a 
direct help to nature, as money, but is invented by the art of man, for 
the convenience of exchange, and as a measure of things salable.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Body Para. 2/3

 Now it is evident that man's happiness cannot consist in natural wealth. 
For wealth of this kind is sought for the sake of something else, viz. as 
a support of human nature: consequently it cannot be man's last end, 
rather is it ordained to man as to its end. Wherefore in the order of 
nature, all such things are below man, and made for him, according to Ps. 
8:8: "Thou hast subjected all things under his feet."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] Body Para. 3/3 

 And as to artificial wealth, it is not sought save for the sake of 
natural wealth; since man would not seek it except because, by its means, 
he procures for himself the necessaries of life. Consequently much less 
can it be considered in the light of the last end. Therefore it is 
impossible for happiness, which is the last end of man, to consist in 
wealth.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: All material things obey money, so far as the multitude of 
fools is concerned, who know no other than material goods, which can be 
obtained for money. But we should take our estimation of human goods not 
from the foolish but from the wise: just as it is for a person whose 
sense of taste is in good order, to judge whether a thing is palatable.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: All things salable can be had for money: not so spiritual 
things, which cannot be sold. Hence it is written (Prov. 17:16): "What 
doth it avail a fool to have riches, seeing he cannot buy wisdom."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The desire for natural riches is not infinite: because they 
suffice for nature in a certain measure. But the desire for artificial 
wealth is infinite, for it is the servant of disordered concupiscence, 
which is not curbed, as the Philosopher makes clear (Polit. i, 3). Yet 
this desire for wealth is infinite otherwise than the desire for the 
sovereign good. For the more perfectly the sovereign good is possessed, 
the more it is loved, and other things despised: because the more we 
possess it, the more we know it. Hence it is written (Ecclus. 24:29): 
"They that eat me shall yet hunger." Whereas in the desire for wealth and 
for whatsoever temporal goods, the contrary is the case: for when we 
already possess them, we despise them, and seek others: which is the 
sense of Our Lord's words (Jn. 4:13): "Whosoever drinketh of this water," 
by which temporal goods are signified, "shall thirst again." The reason 
of this is that we realize more their insufficiency when we possess them: 
and this very fact shows that they are imperfect, and the sovereign good 
does not consist therein.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether man's happiness consists in honors?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that man's happiness consists in honors. For 
happiness or bliss is "the reward of virtue," as the Philosopher says 
(Ethic. i, 9). But honor more than anything else seems to be that by 
which virtue is rewarded, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 3). 
Therefore happiness consists especially in honor.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, that which belongs to God and to persons of great 
excellence seems especially to be happiness, which is the perfect good. 
But that is honor, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 3). Moreover, the 
Apostle says (1 Tim. 1:17): "To . . . the only God be honor and glory." 
Therefore happiness consists in honor. 

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, that which man desires above all is happiness. But 
nothing seems more desirable to man than honor: since man suffers loss in 
all other things, lest he should suffer loss of honor. Therefore 
happiness consists in honor.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Happiness is in the happy. But honor is not in the 
honored, but rather in him who honors, and who offers deference to the 
person honored, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. i, 5). Therefore 
happiness does not consist in honor.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It is impossible for happiness to consist in honor. For 
honor is given to a man on account of some excellence in him; and 
consequently it is a sign and attestation of the excellence that is in 
the person honored. Now a man's excellence is in proportion, especially 
to his happiness, which is man's perfect good; and to its parts, i.e. 
those goods by which he has a certain share of happiness. And therefore 
honor can result from happiness, but happiness cannot principally consist 
therein.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As the Philosopher says (Ethic. i, 5), honor is not that 
reward of virtue, for which the virtuous work: but they receive honor 
from men by way of reward, "as from those who have nothing greater to 
offer." But virtue's true reward is happiness itself, for which the 
virtuous work: whereas if they worked for honor, it would no longer be a 
virtue, but ambition.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Honor is due to God and to persons of great excellence as a 
sign of attestation of excellence already existing: not that honor makes 
them excellent.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: That man desires honor above all else, arises from his 
natural desire for happiness, from which honor results, as stated above. 
Wherefore man seeks to be honored especially by the wise, on whose 
judgment he believes himself to be excellent or happy.


Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether man's happiness consists in fame or glory?

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It would seem that man's happiness consists in glory. For 
happiness seems to consist in that which is paid to the saints for the 
trials they have undergone in the world. But this is glory: for the 
Apostle says (Rm. 8:18): "The sufferings of this time are not worthy to 
be compared with the glory to come, that shall be revealed in us." 
Therefore happiness consists in glory.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, good is diffusive of itself, as stated by Dionysius 
(Div. Nom. iv). But man's good is spread abroad in the knowledge of 
others by glory more than by anything else: since, according to Ambrose 
[*Augustine, Contra Maxim. Arian. ii. 13], glory consists "in being well 
known and praised." Therefore man's happiness consists in glory.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1 

 OBJ 3: Further, happiness is the most enduring good. Now this seems to 
be fame or glory; because by this men attain to eternity after a fashion. 
Hence Boethius says (De Consol. ii): "You seem to beget unto yourselves 
eternity, when you think of your fame in future time." Therefore man's 
happiness consists in fame or glory.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Happiness is man's true good. But it happens that fame 
or glory is false: for as Boethius says (De Consol. iii), "many owe their 
renown to the lying reports spread among the people. Can anything be more 
shameful? For those who receive false fame, must needs blush at their own 
praise." Therefore man's happiness does not consist in fame or glory.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 1/2

 I answer that, Man's happiness cannot consist in human fame or glory. 
For glory consists "in being well known and praised," as Ambrose 
[*Augustine, Contra Maxim. Arian. ii, 13] says. Now the thing known is 
related to human knowledge otherwise than to God's knowledge: for human 
knowledge is caused by the things known, whereas God's knowledge is the 
cause of the things known. Wherefore the perfection of human good, which 
is called happiness, cannot be caused by human knowledge: but rather 
human knowledge of another's happiness proceeds from, and, in a fashion, 
is caused by, human happiness itself, inchoate or perfect. Consequently 
man's happiness cannot consist in fame or glory. On the other hand, man's 
good depends on God's knowledge as its cause. And therefore man's 
beatitude depends, as on its cause, on the glory which man has with God; 
according to Ps. 90:15,16: "I will deliver him, and I will glorify him; I 
will fill him with length of days, and I will show him my salvation."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 2/2

 Furthermore, we must observe that human knowledge often fails, 
especially in contingent singulars, such as are human acts. For this 
reason human glory is frequently deceptive. But since God cannot be 
deceived, His glory is always true; hence it is written (2 Cor. 10:18): 
"He . . . is approved . . . whom God commendeth."

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The Apostle speaks, then, not of the glory which is with 
men, but of the glory which is from God, with His Angels. Hence it is 
written (Mk. 8:38): "The Son of Man shall confess him in the glory of His 
Father, before His angels" [*St. Thomas joins Mk. 8:38 with Lk. 12:8 
owing to a possible variant in his text, or to the fact that he was 
quoting from memory].

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: A man's good which, through fame or glory, is in the 
knowledge of many, if this knowledge be true, must needs be derived from 
good existing in the man himself: and hence it presupposes perfect or 
inchoate happiness. But if the knowledge be false, it does not harmonize 
with the thing: and thus good does not exist in him who is looked upon as 
famous. Hence it follows that fame can nowise make man happy.

Aquin.: SMT FS Q[2] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Fame has no stability; in fact, it is easily ruined by 
false report. And if sometimes it endures, this is by accident. But 
happiness endures of itself, and for ever.