Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] Out. Para. 1/1

SUMMA THEOLOGICA (Benziger Bros. edition, 1947)



FIRST PART (FP: QQ 1-119)


TREATISE ON SACRED DOCTRINE (Q[1])


THE NATURE AND EXTENT OF SACRED DOCTRINE (TEN ARTICLES)

 To place our purpose within proper limits, we first endeavor to 
investigate the nature and extent of this sacred doctrine. Concerning 
this there are ten points of inquiry: 

 (1) Whether it is necessary?

 (2) Whether it is a science?

 (3) Whether it is one or many?

 (4) Whether it is speculative or practical?

 (5) How it is compared with other sciences?

 (6) Whether it is the same as wisdom?

 (7) Whether God is its subject-matter?

 (8) Whether it is a matter of argument?

 (9) Whether it rightly employs metaphors and similes?

 (10) Whether the Sacred Scripture of this doctrine may be expounded in 
different senses?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether, besides philosophy, any further doctrine is required?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that, besides philosophical science, we have no need of 
any further knowledge. For man should not seek to know what is above 
reason: "Seek not the things that are too high for thee" (Ecclus. 3:22). 
But whatever is not above reason is fully treated of in philosophical 
science. Therefore any other knowledge besides philosophical science is 
superfluous.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, knowledge can be concerned only with being, for nothing 
can be known, save what is true; and all that is, is true. But everything 
that is, is treated of in philosophical science---even God Himself; so 
that there is a part of philosophy called theology, or the divine 
science, as Aristotle has proved (Metaph. vi). Therefore, besides 
philosophical science, there is no need of any further knowledge.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written (2 Tim. 3:16): "All Scripture, inspired 
of God is profitable to teach, to reprove, to correct, to instruct in 
justice." Now Scripture, inspired of God, is no part of philosophical 
science, which has been built up by human reason. Therefore it is useful 
that besides philosophical science, there should be other knowledge, i.e. 
inspired of God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It was necessary for man's salvation that there should be 
a knowledge revealed by God besides philosophical science built up by 
human reason. Firstly, indeed, because man is directed to God, as to an 
end that surpasses the grasp of his reason: "The eye hath not seen, O 
God, besides Thee, what things Thou hast prepared for them that wait for 
Thee" (Is. 66:4). But the end must first be known by men who are to 
direct their thoughts and actions to the end. Hence it was necessary for 
the salvation of man that certain truths which exceed human reason should 
be made known to him by divine revelation. Even as regards those truths 
about God which human reason could have discovered, it was necessary that 
man should be taught by a divine revelation; because the truth about God 
such as reason could discover, would only be known by a few, and that 
after a long time, and with the admixture of many errors. Whereas man's 
whole salvation, which is in God, depends upon the knowledge of this 
truth. Therefore, in order that the salvation of men might be brought 
about more fitly and more surely, it was  necessary that they should be 
taught divine truths by divine revelation. It was therefore necessary 
that besides philosophical science built up by reason, there should be a 
sacred science learned through revelation.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Although those things which are beyond man's knowledge may 
not be sought for by man through his reason, nevertheless, once they are 
revealed by God, they must be accepted by faith. Hence the sacred text 
continues, "For many things are shown to thee above the understanding of 
man" (Ecclus. 3:25). And in this, the sacred science consists.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Sciences are differentiated according to the various means 
through which knowledge is obtained. For the astronomer and the physicist 
both may prove the same conclusion: that the earth, for instance, is 
round: the astronomer by means of mathematics (i.e. abstracting from 
matter), but the physicist by means of matter itself. Hence there is no 
reason why those things which may be learned from philosophical science, 
so far as they can be known by natural reason, may not also be taught us 
by another science so far as they fall within revelation. Hence theology 
included in sacred doctrine differs in kind from that theology which is 
part of philosophy.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sacred doctrine is a science?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not a science. For every science 
proceeds from self-evident principles. But sacred doctrine proceeds from 
articles of faith which are not self-evident, since their truth is not 
admitted by all: "For all men have not faith" (2 Thess. 3:2). Therefore 
sacred doctrine is not a science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, no science deals with individual facts. But this sacred 
science treats of individual facts, such as the deeds of Abraham, Isaac 
and Jacob and such like. Therefore sacred doctrine is not a science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. xiv, 1) "to this science alone 
belongs that whereby saving faith is begotten, nourished, protected and 
strengthened." But this can be said of no science except sacred doctrine. 
Therefore sacred doctrine is a science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Sacred doctrine is a science. We must bear in mind that 
there are two kinds of sciences. There are some which proceed from a 
principle known by the natural light of intelligence, such as arithmetic 
and geometry and the like. There are some which proceed from principles 
known by the light of a higher science: thus the science of perspective 
proceeds from principles established by geometry, and music from 
principles established by arithmetic. So it is that sacred doctrine is a 
science because it proceeds from principles established by the  light of 
a higher science, namely, the science of God and the blessed. Hence, just 
as the musician accepts on authority the principles taught him by the 
mathematician, so sacred science is established on principles revealed by 
God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The principles of any science are either in themselves 
self-evident, or reducible to the conclusions of a higher science; and 
such, as we have said, are the principles of sacred doctrine.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Individual facts are treated of in sacred doctrine, not 
because it is concerned with them principally, but they are introduced 
rather both as examples to be followed in our lives (as in moral 
sciences) and in order to establish the authority of those men through 
whom the divine revelation, on which this sacred scripture or doctrine is 
based, has come down to us.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sacred doctrine is one science?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not one science; for according 
to the Philosopher (Poster. i) "that science is one which treats only of 
one class of subjects." But the creator and the creature, both of whom 
are treated of in sacred doctrine, cannot be grouped together under one 
class of subjects. Therefore sacred doctrine is not one science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, in sacred doctrine we treat of angels, corporeal 
creatures and human morality. But these belong to separate philosophical 
sciences. Therefore sacred doctrine cannot be one science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Holy Scripture speaks of it as one science: "Wisdom 
gave him the knowledge [scientiam] of holy things" (Wis. 10:10).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Sacred doctrine is one science. The unity of a faculty or 
habit is to be gauged by its object, not indeed, in its material aspect, 
but as regards the precise formality under which it is an object. For 
example, man, ass, stone agree in the one precise formality of being 
colored; and color is the formal object of sight. Therefore, because 
Sacred Scripture considers things precisely under the formality of being 
divinely revealed, whatever has been divinely revealed possesses the one 
precise formality of the object of this science; and therefore is 
included under sacred doctrine as under one science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Sacred doctrine does not treat of God and creatures 
equally, but of God primarily, and of creatures only so far as they are 
referable to God as their beginning or end. Hence the unity of this 
science is not impaired.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Nothing prevents inferior faculties or habits from being 
differentiated by something which falls under a higher  faculty or habit 
as well; because the higher faculty or habit regards the object in its 
more universal formality, as the object of the "common sense" is whatever 
affects the senses, including, therefore, whatever is visible or audible. 
Hence the "common sense," although one faculty, extends to all the 
objects of the five senses. Similarly, objects which are the 
subject-matter of different philosophical sciences can yet be treated of 
by this one single sacred science under one aspect precisely so far as 
they can be included in revelation. So that in this way, sacred doctrine 
bears, as it were, the stamp of the divine science which is one and 
simple, yet extends to everything.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sacred doctrine is a practical science?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that sacred doctrine is a practical science; for a 
practical science is that which ends in action according to the 
Philosopher (Metaph. ii). But sacred doctrine is ordained to action: "Be 
ye doers of the word, and not hearers only" (James 1:22). Therefore 
sacred doctrine is a practical science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, sacred doctrine is divided into the Old and the New Law. 
But law implies a moral science which is a practical science. Therefore 
sacred doctrine is a practical science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Every practical science is concerned with human 
operations; as moral science is concerned with human acts, and 
architecture with buildings. But sacred doctrine is chiefly concerned 
with God, whose handiwork is especially man. Therefore it is not a 
practical but a speculative science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Sacred doctrine, being one, extends to things which 
belong to different philosophical sciences because it considers in each 
the same formal aspect, namely, so far as they can be known through 
divine revelation. Hence, although among the philosophical sciences one 
is speculative and another practical, nevertheless sacred doctrine 
includes both; as God, by one and the same science, knows both Himself 
and His works. Still, it is speculative rather than practical because it 
is more concerned with divine things than with human acts; though it does 
treat even of these latter, inasmuch as man is ordained by them to the 
perfect knowledge of God in which consists eternal bliss. This is a 
sufficient answer to the Objections.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sacred doctrine is nobler than other sciences?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not nobler than other sciences; 
for the nobility of a science depends on the certitude it establishes. 
But other sciences, the principles of which cannot be doubted, seem to be 
more certain than sacred doctrine; for its principles---namely, articles 
of faith---can be doubted. Therefore other sciences seem to be nobler.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1 

 OBJ 2: Further, it is the sign of a lower science to depend upon a 
higher; as music depends on arithmetic. But sacred doctrine does in a 
sense depend upon philosophical sciences; for Jerome observes, in his 
Epistle to Magnus, that "the ancient doctors so enriched their books with 
the ideas and phrases of the philosophers, that thou knowest not what 
more to admire in them, their profane erudition or their scriptural 
learning." Therefore sacred doctrine is inferior to other sciences.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Other sciences are called the handmaidens of this one: 
"Wisdom sent her maids to invite to the tower" (Prov. 9:3).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Since this science is partly speculative and partly 
practical, it transcends all others speculative and practical. Now one 
speculative science is said to be nobler than another, either by reason 
of its greater certitude, or by reason of the higher worth of its 
subject-matter. In both these respects this science surpasses other 
speculative sciences; in point of greater certitude, because other 
sciences derive their certitude from the natural light of human reason, 
which can err; whereas this derives its certitude from the light of 
divine knowledge, which cannot be misled: in point of the higher worth of 
its subject-matter because this science treats chiefly of those things 
which by their sublimity transcend human reason; while other sciences 
consider only those things which are within reason's grasp. Of the 
practical sciences, that one is nobler which is ordained to a further 
purpose, as political science is nobler than military science; for the 
good of the army is directed to the good of the State. But the purpose of 
this science, in so far as it is practical, is eternal bliss; to which as 
to an ultimate end the purposes of every practical science are directed. 
Hence it is clear that from every standpoint, it is nobler than other 
sciences.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: It may well happen that what is in itself the more certain 
may seem to us the less certain on account of the weakness of our 
intelligence, "which is dazzled by the clearest objects of nature; as the 
owl is dazzled by the light of the sun" (Metaph. ii, lect. i). Hence the 
fact that some happen to doubt about articles of faith is not due to the 
uncertain nature of the truths, but to the weakness of human 
intelligence; yet the slenderest knowledge that may be obtained of the 
highest things is more desirable than the most certain knowledge obtained 
of lesser things, as is said in de Animalibus xi.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: This science can in a sense depend upon the philosophical 
sciences, not as though it stood in need of them, but only in order to 
make its teaching clearer. For it accepts its principles not from other 
sciences, but immediately from God, by revelation. Therefore it does not 
depend upon other sciences as upon the higher, but makes use of them as 
of the lesser, and as handmaidens: even so the master sciences make use 
of the sciences that supply their materials, as political of military 
science. That it thus uses them is not due to its own defect or 
insufficiency,  but to the defect of our intelligence, which is more 
easily led by what is known through natural reason (from which proceed 
the other sciences) to that which is above reason, such as are the 
teachings of this science.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether this doctrine is the same as wisdom?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that this doctrine is not the same as wisdom. For no 
doctrine which borrows its principles is worthy of the name of wisdom; 
seeing that the wise man directs, and is not directed (Metaph. i). But 
this doctrine borrows its principles. Therefore this science is not 
wisdom.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, it is a part of wisdom to prove the principles of other 
sciences. Hence it is called the chief of sciences, as is clear in Ethic. 
vi. But this doctrine does not prove the principles of other sciences. 
Therefore it is not the same as wisdom.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, this doctrine is acquired by study, whereas wisdom is 
acquired by God's inspiration; so that it is numbered among the gifts of 
the Holy Spirit (Is. 11:2). Therefore this doctrine is not the same as 
wisdom.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written (Dt. 4:6): "This is your wisdom and 
understanding in the sight of nations."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, This doctrine is wisdom above all human wisdom; not 
merely in any one order, but absolutely. For since it is the part of a 
wise man to arrange and to judge, and since lesser matters should be 
judged in the light of some higher principle, he is said to be wise in 
any one order who considers the highest principle in that order: thus in 
the order of building, he who plans the form of the house is called wise 
and architect, in opposition to the inferior laborers who trim the wood 
and make ready the stones: "As a wise architect, I have laid the 
foundation" (1 Cor. 3:10). Again, in the order of all human life, the 
prudent man is called wise, inasmuch as he directs his acts to a fitting 
end: "Wisdom is prudence to a man" (Prov. 10: 23). Therefore he who 
considers absolutely the highest cause of the whole universe, namely God, 
is most of all called wise. Hence wisdom is said to be the knowledge of 
divine things, as Augustine says (De Trin. xii, 14). But sacred doctrine 
essentially treats of God viewed as the highest cause---not only so far 
as He can be known through creatures just as philosophers knew 
Him---"That which is known of God is manifest in them" (Rm. 1:19)---but 
also as far as He is known to Himself alone and revealed to others. Hence 
sacred doctrine is especially called wisdom.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Sacred doctrine derives its principles not from any human 
knowledge, but from the divine knowledge, through which, as through the 
highest wisdom, all our knowledge is set in order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The principles of other sciences either are  evident and 
cannot be proved, or are proved by natural reason through some other 
science. But the knowledge proper to this science comes through 
revelation and not through natural reason. Therefore it has no concern to 
prove the principles of other sciences, but only to judge of them. 
Whatsoever is found in other sciences contrary to any truth of this 
science must be condemned as false: "Destroying counsels and every height 
that exalteth itself against the knowledge of God" (2 Cor. 10:4,5).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Since judgment appertains to wisdom, the twofold manner of 
judging produces a twofold wisdom. A man may judge in one way by 
inclination, as whoever has the habit of a virtue judges rightly of what 
concerns that virtue by his very inclination towards it. Hence it is the 
virtuous man, as we read, who is the measure and rule of human acts. In 
another way, by knowledge, just as a man learned in moral science might 
be able to judge rightly about virtuous acts, though he had not the 
virtue. The first manner of judging divine things belongs to that wisdom 
which is set down among the gifts of the Holy Ghost: "The spiritual man 
judgeth all things" (1 Cor. 2:15). And Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ii): 
"Hierotheus is taught not by mere learning, but by experience of divine 
things." The second manner of judging belongs to this doctrine which is 
acquired by study, though its principles are obtained by revelation.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is the object of this science?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is not the object of this science. For in every 
science, the nature of its object is presupposed. But this science cannot 
presuppose the essence of God, for Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, iv): 
"It is impossible to define the essence of God." Therefore God is not the 
object of this science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, whatever conclusions are reached in any science must be 
comprehended under the object of the science. But in Holy Writ we reach 
conclusions not only concerning God, but concerning many other things, 
such as creatures and human morality. Therefore God is not the object of 
this science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The object of the science is that of which it 
principally treats. But in this science, the treatment is mainly about 
God; for it is called theology, as treating of God. Therefore God is the 
object of this science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, God is the object of this science. The relation between a 
science and its object is the same as that between a habit or faculty and 
its object. Now properly speaking, the object of a faculty or habit is 
the thing under the aspect of which all things are referred to that 
faculty or habit, as man and stone are referred to the faculty of sight 
in that they are colored. Hence colored things are the proper objects of 
sight. But in sacred science, all things are treated of under the aspect 
of God: either because they are God Himself or because they refer to God 
as their  beginning and end. Hence it follows that God is in very truth 
the object of this science. This is clear also from the principles of 
this science, namely, the articles of faith, for faith is about God. The 
object of the principles and of the whole science must be the same, since 
the whole science is contained virtually in its principles. Some, 
however, looking to what is treated of in this science, and not to the 
aspect under which it is treated, have asserted the object of this 
science to be something other than God---that is, either things and 
signs; or the works of salvation; or the whole Christ, as the head and 
members. Of all these things, in truth, we treat in this science, but so 
far as they have reference to God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Although we cannot know in what consists the essence of 
God, nevertheless in this science we make use of His effects, either of 
nature or of grace, in place of a definition, in regard to whatever is 
treated of in this science concerning God; even as in some philosophical 
sciences we demonstrate something about a cause from its effect, by 
taking the effect in place of a definition of the cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Whatever other conclusions are reached in this sacred 
science are comprehended under God, not as parts or species or accidents 
but as in some way related to Him.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether sacred doctrine is a matter of argument?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems this doctrine is not a matter of argument. For Ambrose 
says (De Fide 1): "Put arguments aside where faith is sought." But in 
this doctrine, faith especially is sought: "But these things are written 
that you may believe" (Jn. 20:31). Therefore sacred doctrine is not a 
matter of argument.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, if it is a matter of argument, the argument is either 
from authority or from reason. If it is from authority, it seems 
unbefitting its dignity, for the proof from authority is the weakest form 
of proof. But if it is from reason, this is unbefitting its end, because, 
according to Gregory (Hom. 26), "faith has no merit in those things of 
which human reason brings its own experience." Therefore sacred doctrine 
is not a matter of argument.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Scripture says that a bishop should "embrace that 
faithful word which is according to doctrine, that he may be able to 
exhort in sound doctrine and to convince the gainsayers" (Titus 1:9).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, As other sciences do not argue in proof of their 
principles, but argue from their principles to demonstrate other truths 
in these sciences: so this doctrine does not argue in proof of its 
principles, which are the articles of faith, but from them it goes on to 
prove something else; as the Apostle from the resurrection of Christ 
argues in proof of the general resurrection  (1 Cor. 15). However, it is 
to be borne in mind, in regard to the philosophical sciences, that the 
inferior sciences neither prove their principles nor dispute with those 
who deny them, but leave this to a higher science; whereas the highest of 
them, viz. metaphysics, can dispute with one who denies its principles, 
if only the opponent will make some concession; but if he concede 
nothing, it can have no dispute with him, though it can answer his 
objections. Hence Sacred Scripture, since it has no science above itself, 
can dispute with one who denies its principles only if the opponent 
admits some at least of the truths obtained through divine revelation; 
thus we can argue with heretics from texts in Holy Writ, and against 
those who deny one article of faith, we can argue from another. If our 
opponent believes nothing of divine revelation, there is no longer any 
means of proving the articles of faith by reasoning, but only of 
answering his objections---if he has any---against faith. Since faith 
rests upon infallible truth, and since the contrary of a truth can never 
be demonstrated, it is clear that the arguments brought against faith 
cannot be demonstrations, but are difficulties that can be answered.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Although arguments from human reason cannot avail to prove 
what must be received on faith, nevertheless, this doctrine argues from 
articles of faith to other truths.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: This doctrine is especially based upon arguments from 
authority, inasmuch as its principles are obtained by revelation: thus we 
ought to believe on the authority of those to whom the revelation has 
been made. Nor does this take away from the dignity of this doctrine, for 
although the argument from authority based on human reason is the 
weakest, yet the argument from authority based on divine revelation is 
the strongest. But sacred doctrine makes use even of human reason, not, 
indeed, to prove faith (for thereby the merit of faith would come to an 
end), but to make clear other things that are put forward in this 
doctrine. Since therefore grace does not destroy nature but perfects it, 
natural reason should minister to faith as the natural bent of the will 
ministers to charity. Hence the Apostle says: "Bringing into captivity 
every understanding unto the obedience of Christ" (2 Cor. 10:5). Hence 
sacred doctrine makes use also of the authority of philosophers in those 
questions in which they were able to know the truth by natural reason, as 
Paul quotes a saying of Aratus: "As some also of your own poets said: For 
we are also His offspring" (Acts 17:28). Nevertheless, sacred doctrine 
makes use of these authorities as extrinsic and probable arguments; but 
properly uses the authority of the canonical Scriptures as an 
incontrovertible proof, and the authority of the doctors of the Church as 
one that may properly be used, yet merely as probable. For our faith 
rests upon the revelation made to the apostles and prophets who wrote the 
canonical books, and not on the revelations (if any such there are) made 
to other doctors. Hence Augustine says (Epis. ad Hieron. xix, 1): "Only 
those books of Scripture which are called canonical have I learned to 
hold in such honor as to believe their authors have not erred in any way 
in writing them. But other authors I so read as not to deem everything in 
their works to be true, merely on  account of their having so thought and 
written, whatever may have been their holiness and learning."


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether Holy Scripture should use metaphors?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that Holy Scripture should not use metaphors. For that 
which is proper to the lowest science seems not to befit this science, 
which holds the highest place of all. But to proceed by the aid of 
various similitudes and figures is proper to poetry, the least of all the 
sciences. Therefore it is not fitting that this science should make use 
of such similitudes.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, this doctrine seems to be intended to make truth clear. 
Hence a reward is held out to those who manifest it: "They that explain 
me shall have life everlasting" (Ecclus. 24:31). But by such similitudes 
truth is obscured. Therefore, to put forward divine truths by likening 
them to corporeal things does not befit this science.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, the higher creatures are, the nearer they approach to 
the divine likeness. If therefore any creature be taken to represent God, 
this representation ought chiefly to be taken from the higher creatures, 
and not from the lower; yet this is often found in Scriptures.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written (Osee 12:10): "I have multiplied visions, 
and I have used similitudes by the ministry of the prophets." But to put 
forward anything by means of similitudes is to use metaphors. Therefore 
this sacred science may use metaphors.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It is befitting Holy Writ to put forward divine and 
spiritual truths by means of comparisons with material things. For God 
provides for everything according to the capacity of its nature. Now it 
is natural to man to attain to intellectual truths through sensible 
objects, because all our knowledge originates from sense. Hence in Holy 
Writ, spiritual truths are fittingly taught under the likeness of 
material things. This is what Dionysius says (Coel. Hier. i): "We cannot 
be enlightened by the divine rays except they be hidden within the 
covering of many sacred veils." It is also befitting Holy Writ, which is 
proposed to all without distinction of persons---"To the wise and to the 
unwise I am a debtor" (Rm. 1:14)---that spiritual truths be expounded by 
means of figures taken from corporeal things, in order that thereby even 
the simple who are unable by themselves to grasp intellectual things may 
be able to understand it.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Poetry makes use of metaphors to produce a representation, 
for it is natural to man to be pleased with representations. But sacred 
doctrine makes use of metaphors as both necessary and useful.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The ray of divine revelation is not extinguished  by the 
sensible imagery wherewith it is veiled, as Dionysius says (Coel. Hier. 
i); and its truth so far remains that it does not allow the minds of 
those to whom the revelation has been made, to rest in the metaphors, but 
raises them to the knowledge of truths; and through those to whom the 
revelation has been made others also may receive instruction in these 
matters. Hence those things that are taught metaphorically in one part of 
Scripture, in other parts are taught more openly. The very hiding of 
truth in figures is useful for the exercise of thoughtful minds and as a 
defense against the ridicule of the impious, according to the words "Give 
not that which is holy to dogs" (Mt. 7:6).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[9] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: As Dionysius says, (Coel. Hier. i) it is more fitting that 
divine truths should be expounded under the figure of less noble than of 
nobler bodies, and this for three reasons. Firstly, because thereby men's 
minds are the better preserved from error. For then it is clear that 
these things are not literal descriptions of divine truths, which might 
have been open to doubt had they been expressed under the figure of 
nobler bodies, especially for those who could think of nothing nobler 
than bodies. Secondly, because this is more befitting the knowledge of 
God that we have in this life. For what He is not is clearer to us than 
what He is. Therefore similitudes drawn from things farthest away from 
God form within us a truer estimate that God is above whatsoever we may 
say or think of Him. Thirdly, because thereby divine truths are the 
better hidden from the unworthy.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether in Holy Scripture a word may have several senses?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that in Holy Writ a word cannot have several senses, 
historical or literal, allegorical, tropological or moral, and 
anagogical. For many different senses in one text produce confusion and 
deception and destroy all force of argument. Hence no argument, but only 
fallacies, can be deduced from a multiplicity of propositions. But Holy 
Writ ought to be able to state the truth without any fallacy. Therefore 
in it there cannot be several senses to a word.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, Augustine says (De util. cred. iii) that "the Old 
Testament has a fourfold division as to history, etiology, analogy and 
allegory." Now these four seem altogether different from the four 
divisions mentioned in the first objection. Therefore it does not seem 
fitting to explain the same word of Holy Writ according to the four 
different senses mentioned above.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, besides these senses, there is the parabolical, which is 
not one of these four.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Gregory says (Moral. xx, 1): "Holy Writ by the manner 
of its speech transcends every science, because in one and the same 
sentence, while it describes a fact, it reveals a mystery."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] Body Para. 1/1 

 I answer that, The author of Holy Writ is God, in whose power it is to 
signify His meaning, not by words only (as man also can do), but also by 
things themselves. So, whereas in every other science things are 
signified by words, this science has the property, that the things 
signified by the words have themselves also a signification. Therefore 
that first signification whereby words signify things belongs to the 
first sense, the historical or literal. That signification whereby things 
signified by words have themselves also a signification is called the 
spiritual sense, which is based on the literal, and presupposes it. Now 
this spiritual sense has a threefold division. For as the Apostle says 
(Heb. 10:1) the Old Law is a figure of the New Law, and Dionysius says 
(Coel. Hier. i) "the New Law itself is a figure of future glory." Again, 
in the New Law, whatever our Head has done is a type of what we ought to 
do. Therefore, so far as the things of the Old Law signify the things of 
the New Law, there is the allegorical sense; so far as the things done in 
Christ, or so far as the things which signify Christ, are types of what 
we ought to do, there is the moral sense. But so far as they signify what 
relates to eternal glory, there is the anagogical sense. Since the 
literal sense is that which the author intends, and since the author of 
Holy Writ is God, Who by one act comprehends all things by His intellect, 
it is not unfitting, as Augustine says (Confess. xii), if, even according 
to the literal sense, one word in Holy Writ should have several senses.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The multiplicity of these senses does not produce 
equivocation or any other kind of multiplicity, seeing that these senses 
are not multiplied because one word signifies several things, but because 
the things signified by the words can be themselves types of other 
things. Thus in Holy Writ no confusion results, for all the senses are 
founded on one---the literal---from which alone can any argument be 
drawn, and not from those intended in allegory, as Augustine says (Epis. 
48). Nevertheless, nothing of Holy Scripture perishes on account of this, 
since nothing necessary to faith is contained under the spiritual sense 
which is not elsewhere put forward by the Scripture in its literal sense.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: These three---history, etiology, analogy---are grouped 
under the literal sense. For it is called history, as Augustine expounds 
(Epis. 48), whenever anything is simply related; it is called etiology 
when its cause is assigned, as when Our Lord gave the reason why Moses 
allowed the putting away of wives---namely, on account of the hardness of 
men's hearts; it is called analogy whenever the truth of one text of 
Scripture is shown not to contradict the truth of another. Of these four, 
allegory alone stands for the three spiritual senses. Thus Hugh of St. 
Victor (Sacram. iv, 4 Prolog.) includes the anagogical under the 
allegorical sense, laying down three senses only---the historical, the 
allegorical, and the tropological.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[1] A[10] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The parabolical sense is contained in the literal, for by 
words things are signified properly and figuratively. Nor is the figure 
itself, but that which is figured,  the literal sense. When Scripture 
speaks of God's arm, the literal sense is not that God has such a member, 
but only what is signified by this member, namely operative power. Hence 
it is plain that nothing false can ever underlie the literal sense of 
Holy Writ.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] Out. Para. 1/4

TREATISE ON THE ONE GOD (QQ[2]-26)


THE EXISTENCE OF GOD (THREE ARTICLES)

 Because the chief aim of sacred doctrine is to teach the knowledge of 
God, not only as He is in Himself, but also as He is the beginning of 
things and their last end, and especially of rational creatures, as is 
clear from what has been already said, therefore, in our endeavor to 
expound this science, we shall treat: (1) Of God; (2) Of the rational 
creature's advance towards God; (3) Of Christ, Who as man, is our way to 
God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] Out. Para. 2/4

 In treating of God there will be a threefold division, for we shall 
consider: (1) Whatever concerns the Divine Essence; (2) Whatever concerns 
the distinctions of Persons; (3) Whatever concerns the procession of 
creatures from Him.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] Out. Para. 3/4

 Concerning the Divine Essence, we must consider: (1) Whether God exists? 
(2) The manner of His existence, or, rather, what is NOT the manner of 
His existence; (3) Whatever concerns His operations---namely, His 
knowledge, will, power.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] Out. Para. 4/4

 Concerning the first, there are three points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether the proposition "God exists" is self-evident?

 (2) Whether it is demonstrable?

 (3) Whether God exists?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the existence of God is self-evident?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that the existence of God is self-evident. Now those 
things are said to be self-evident to us the knowledge of which is 
naturally implanted in us, as we can see in regard to first principles. 
But as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, 1,3), "the knowledge of God is 
naturally implanted in all." Therefore the existence of God is 
self-evident.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, those things are said to be self-evident which are known 
as soon as the terms are known, which the Philosopher (1 Poster. iii) 
says is true of the first principles of demonstration. Thus, when the 
nature of a whole and of a part is known, it is at once recognized that 
every whole is greater than its part. But as soon as the signification of 
the word "God" is understood, it is at once seen that God exists. For by 
this word is signified that thing than which nothing greater can be 
conceived. But that which exists actually and mentally is greater than 
that which exists only mentally. Therefore, since as soon as the word 
"God" is understood it exists mentally, it also follows that it exists 
actually. Therefore the proposition "God exists" is self-evident. 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, the existence of truth is self-evident. For whoever 
denies the existence of truth grants that truth does not exist: and, if 
truth does not exist, then the proposition "Truth does not exist" is 
true: and if there is anything true, there must be truth. But God is 
truth itself: "I am the way, the truth, and the life" (Jn. 14:6) 
Therefore "God exists" is self-evident.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, No one can mentally admit the opposite of what is 
self-evident; as the Philosopher (Metaph. iv, lect. vi) states concerning 
the first principles of demonstration. But the opposite of the 
proposition "God is" can be mentally admitted: "The fool said in his 
heart, There is no God" (Ps. 52:1). Therefore, that God exists is not 
self-evident.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, A thing can be self-evident in either of two ways: on the 
one hand, self-evident in itself, though not to us; on the other, 
self-evident in itself, and to us. A proposition is self-evident because 
the predicate is included in the essence of the subject, as "Man is an 
animal," for animal is contained in the essence of man. If, therefore the 
essence of the predicate and subject be known to all, the proposition 
will be self-evident to all; as is clear with regard to the first 
principles of demonstration, the terms of which are common things that no 
one is ignorant of, such as being and non-being, whole and part, and such 
like. If, however, there are some to whom the essence of the predicate 
and subject is unknown, the proposition will be self-evident in itself, 
but not to those who do not know the meaning of the predicate and subject 
of the proposition. Therefore, it happens, as Boethius says (Hebdom., the 
title of which is: "Whether all that is, is good"), "that there are some 
mental concepts self-evident only to the learned, as that incorporeal 
substances are not in space." Therefore I say that this proposition, "God 
exists," of itself is self-evident, for the predicate is the same as the 
subject, because God is His own existence as will be hereafter shown 
(Q[3], A[4]). Now because we do not know the essence of God, the 
proposition is not self-evident to us; but needs to be demonstrated by 
things that are more known to us, though less known in their 
nature---namely, by effects.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: To know that God exists in a general and confused way is 
implanted in us by nature, inasmuch as God is man's beatitude. For man 
naturally desires happiness, and what is naturally desired by man must be 
naturally known to him. This, however, is not to know absolutely that God 
exists; just as to know that someone is approaching is not the same as to 
know that Peter is approaching, even though it is Peter who is 
approaching; for many there are who imagine that man's perfect good which 
is happiness, consists in riches, and others in pleasures, and others in 
something else.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Perhaps not everyone who hears this word "God" understands 
it to signify something than which nothing greater can be thought, seeing 
that some have believed God to be a body. Yet,  granted that everyone 
understands that by this word "God" is signified something than which 
nothing greater can be thought, nevertheless, it does not therefore 
follow that he understands that what the word signifies exists actually, 
but only that it exists mentally. Nor can it be argued that it actually 
exists, unless it be admitted that there actually exists something than 
which nothing greater can be thought; and this precisely is not admitted 
by those who hold that God does not exist.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The existence of truth in general is self-evident but the 
existence of a Primal Truth is not self-evident to us.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether it can be demonstrated that God exists?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that the existence of God cannot be demonstrated. For it 
is an article of faith that God exists. But what is of faith cannot be 
demonstrated, because a demonstration produces scientific knowledge; 
whereas faith is of the unseen (Heb. 11:1). Therefore it cannot be 
demonstrated that God exists.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, the essence is the middle term of demonstration. But we 
cannot know in what God's essence consists, but solely in what it does 
not consist; as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, 4). Therefore we cannot 
demonstrate that God exists.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, if the existence of God were demonstrated, this could 
only be from His effects. But His effects are not proportionate to Him, 
since He is infinite and His effects are finite; and between the finite 
and infinite there is no proportion. Therefore, since a cause cannot be 
demonstrated by an effect not proportionate to it, it seems that the 
existence of God cannot be demonstrated.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Apostle says: "The invisible things of Him are 
clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made" (Rm. 1:20). 
But this would not be unless the existence of God could be demonstrated 
through the things that are made; for the first thing we must know of 
anything is whether it exists.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Demonstration can be made in two ways: One is through the 
cause, and is called "a priori," and this is to argue from what is prior 
absolutely. The other is through the effect, and is called a 
demonstration "a posteriori"; this is to argue from what is prior 
relatively only to us. When an effect is better known to us than its 
cause, from the effect we proceed to the knowledge of the cause. And from 
every effect the existence of its proper cause can be demonstrated, so 
long as its effects are better known to us; because since every effect 
depends upon its cause, if the effect exists, the cause must pre-exist. 
Hence the existence of God, in so far as it is not self-evident to us, 
can be demonstrated from those of His effects which are known to us.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The existence of God and other like truths about  God, 
which can be known by natural reason, are not articles of faith, but are 
preambles to the articles; for faith presupposes natural knowledge, even 
as grace presupposes nature, and perfection supposes something that can 
be perfected. Nevertheless, there is nothing to prevent a man, who cannot 
grasp a proof, accepting, as a matter of faith, something which in itself 
is capable of being scientifically known and demonstrated.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: When the existence of a cause is demonstrated from an 
effect, this effect takes the place of the definition of the cause in 
proof of the cause's existence. This is especially the case in regard to 
God, because, in order to prove the existence of anything, it is 
necessary to accept as a middle term the meaning of the word, and not its 
essence, for the question of its essence follows on the question of its 
existence. Now the names given to God are derived from His effects; 
consequently, in demonstrating the existence of God from His effects, we 
may take for the middle term the meaning of the word "God".

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: From effects not proportionate to the cause no perfect 
knowledge of that cause can be obtained. Yet from every effect the 
existence of the cause can be clearly demonstrated, and so we can 
demonstrate the existence of God from His effects; though from them we 
cannot perfectly know God as He is in His essence.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God exists?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God does not exist; because if one of two 
contraries be infinite, the other would be altogether destroyed. But the 
word "God" means that He is infinite goodness. If, therefore, God 
existed, there would be no evil discoverable; but there is evil in the 
world. Therefore God does not exist.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted 
for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that 
everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles, 
supposing God did not exist. For all natural things can be reduced to one 
principle which is nature; and all voluntary things can be reduced to one 
principle which is human reason, or will. Therefore there is no need to 
suppose God's existence.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is said in the person of God: "I am Who am." (Ex. 
3:14)

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 1/6

 I answer that, The existence of God can be proved in five ways.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 2/6

 The first and more manifest way is the argument from motion. It is 
certain, and evident to our senses, that in the world some things are in 
motion. Now whatever is in motion is put in motion by another, for 
nothing can be in motion except it is in potentiality to that towards 
which it is in motion; whereas a thing moves  inasmuch as it is in act. 
For motion is nothing else than the reduction of something from 
potentiality to actuality. But nothing can be reduced from potentiality 
to actuality, except by something in a state of actuality. Thus that 
which is actually hot, as fire, makes wood, which is potentially hot, to 
be actually hot, and thereby moves and changes it. Now it is not possible 
that the same thing should be at once in actuality and potentiality in 
the same respect, but only in different respects. For what is actually 
hot cannot simultaneously be potentially hot; but it is simultaneously 
potentially cold. It is therefore impossible that in the same respect and 
in the same way a thing should be both mover and moved, i.e. that it 
should move itself. Therefore, whatever is in motion must be put in 
motion by another. If that by which it is put in motion be itself put in 
motion, then this also must needs be put in motion by another, and that 
by another again. But this cannot go on to infinity, because then there 
would be no first mover, and, consequently, no other mover; seeing that 
subsequent movers move only inasmuch as they are put in motion by the 
first mover; as the staff moves only because it is put in motion by the 
hand. Therefore it is necessary to arrive at a first mover, put in motion 
by no other; and this everyone understands to be God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 3/6

 The second way is from the nature of the efficient cause. In the world 
of sense we find there is an order of efficient causes. There is no case 
known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be 
the efficient cause of itself; for so it would be prior to itself, which 
is impossible. Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go on to 
infinity, because in all efficient causes following in order, the first 
is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause 
of the ultimate cause, whether the intermediate cause be several, or only 
one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if 
there be no first cause among efficient causes, there will be no 
ultimate, nor any intermediate cause. But if in efficient causes it is 
possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, 
neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient 
causes; all of which is plainly false. Therefore it is necessary to admit 
a first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name of God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 4/6

 The third way is taken from possibility and necessity, and runs thus. We 
find in nature things that are possible to be and not to be, since they 
are found to be generated, and to corrupt, and consequently, they are 
possible to be and not to be. But it is impossible for these always to 
exist, for that which is possible not to be at some time is not. 
Therefore, if everything is possible not to be, then at one time there 
could have been nothing in existence. Now if this were true, even now 
there would be nothing in existence, because that which does not exist 
only begins to exist by something already existing. Therefore, if at one 
time nothing was in existence, it would have been impossible for anything 
to have begun to exist; and thus even now nothing would be in 
existence---which is absurd. Therefore, not all beings are merely 
possible, but there must exist something the existence of  which is 
necessary. But every necessary thing either has its necessity caused by 
another, or not. Now it is impossible to go on to infinity in necessary 
things which have their necessity caused by another, as has been already 
proved in regard to efficient causes. Therefore we cannot but postulate 
the existence of some being having of itself its own necessity, and not 
receiving it from another, but rather causing in others their necessity. 
This all men speak of as God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 5/6

 The fourth way is taken from the gradation to be found in things. Among 
beings there are some more and some less good, true, noble and the like. 
But "more" and "less" are predicated of different things, according as 
they resemble in their different ways something which is the maximum, as 
a thing is said to be hotter according as it more nearly resembles that 
which is hottest; so that there is something which is truest, something 
best, something noblest and, consequently, something which is uttermost 
being; for those things that are greatest in truth are greatest in being, 
as it is written in Metaph. ii. Now the maximum in any genus is the cause 
of all in that genus; as fire, which is the maximum heat, is the cause of 
all hot things. Therefore there must also be something which is to all 
beings the cause of their being, goodness, and every other perfection; 
and this we call God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 6/6

 The fifth way is taken from the governance of the world. We see that 
things which lack intelligence, such as natural bodies, act for an end, 
and this is evident from their acting always, or nearly always, in the 
same way, so as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain that not 
fortuitously, but designedly, do they achieve their end. Now whatever 
lacks intelligence cannot move towards an end, unless it be directed by 
some being endowed with knowledge and intelligence; as the arrow is shot 
to its mark by the archer. Therefore some intelligent being exists by 
whom all natural things are directed to their end; and this being we call 
God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As Augustine says (Enchiridion xi): "Since God is the 
highest good, He would not allow any evil to exist in His works, unless 
His omnipotence and goodness were such as to bring good even out of 
evil." This is part of the infinite goodness of God, that He should allow 
evil to exist, and out of it produce good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Since nature works for a determinate end under the 
direction of a higher agent, whatever is done by nature must needs be 
traced back to God, as to its first cause. So also whatever is done 
voluntarily must also be traced back to some higher cause other than 
human reason or will, since these can change or fail; for all things that 
are changeable and capable of defect must be traced back to an immovable 
and self-necessary first principle, as was shown in the body of the 
Article.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] Out. Para. 1/4

OF THE SIMPLICITY OF GOD (EIGHT ARTICLES)

 When the existence of a thing has been ascertained there  remains the 
further question of the manner of its existence, in order that we may 
know its essence. Now, because we cannot know what God is, but rather 
what He is not, we have no means for considering how God is, but rather 
how He is not.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] Out. Para. 2/4

 Therefore, we must consider: (1) How He is not; (2) How He is known by 
us; (3) How He is named.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] Out. Para. 3/4

 Now it can be shown how God is not, by denying Him whatever is opposed 
to the idea of Him, viz. composition, motion, and the like. Therefore (1) 
we must discuss His simplicity, whereby we deny composition in Him; and 
because whatever is simple in material things is imperfect and a part of 
something else, we shall discuss (2) His perfection; (3) His infinity; 
(4) His immutability; (5) His unity.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] Out. Para. 4/4

 Concerning His simplicity, there are eight points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether God is a body?

 (2) Whether He is composed of matter and form?

 (3) Whether in Him there is composition of quiddity, essence or nature, 
and subject?

 (4) Whether He is composed of essence and existence?

 (5) Whether He is composed of genus and difference?

 (6) Whether He is composed of subject and accident?

 (7) Whether He is in any way composite, or wholly simple?

 (8) Whether He enters into composition with other things?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is a body?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is a body. For a body is that which has the 
three dimensions. But Holy Scripture attributes the three dimensions to 
God, for it is written: "He is higher than Heaven, and what wilt thou do? 
He is deeper than Hell, and how wilt thou know? The measure of Him is 
longer than the earth and broader than the sea" (Job 11:8,9). Therefore 
God is a body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, everything that has figure is a body, since figure is a 
quality of quantity. But God seems to have figure, for it is written: 
"Let us make man to our image and likeness" (Gn. 1:26). Now a figure is 
called an image, according to the text: "Who being the brightness of His 
glory and the figure," i.e. the image, "of His substance" (Heb. 1:3). 
Therefore God is a body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, whatever has corporeal parts is a body. Now Scripture 
attributes corporeal parts to God. "Hast thou an arm like God?" (Job 
40:4); and "The eyes of the Lord are upon the just" (Ps. 33:16); and "The 
right hand of the Lord hath wrought strength" (Ps. 117:16). Therefore God 
is a body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, posture belongs only to bodies. But something which 
supposes posture is said of God in the Scriptures: "I saw the Lord 
sitting" (Is. 6:1), and "He standeth up to judge" (Is. 3:13). Therefore 
God is a body. 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 5: Further, only bodies or things corporeal can be a local term 
"wherefrom" or "whereto." But in the Scriptures God is spoken of as a 
local term "whereto," according to the words, "Come ye to Him and be 
enlightened" (Ps. 33:6), and as a term "wherefrom": "All they that depart 
from Thee shall be written in the earth" (Jer. 17:13). Therefore God is a 
body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written in the Gospel of St. John (Jn. 4:24): 
"God is a spirit."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It is absolutely true that God is not a body; and this 
can be shown in three ways. First, because no body is in motion unless it 
be put in motion, as is evident from induction. Now it has been already 
proved (Q[2], A[3]), that God is the First Mover, and is Himself unmoved. 
Therefore it is clear that God is not a body. Secondly, because the first 
being must of necessity be in act, and in no way in potentiality. For 
although in any single thing that passes from potentiality to actuality, 
the potentiality is prior in time to the actuality; nevertheless, 
absolutely speaking, actuality is prior to potentiality; for whatever is 
in potentiality can be reduced into actuality only by some being in 
actuality. Now it has been already proved that God is the First Being. It 
is therefore impossible that in God there should be any potentiality. But 
every body is in potentiality because the continuous, as such, is 
divisible to infinity; it is therefore impossible that God should be a 
body. Thirdly, because God is the most noble of beings. Now it is 
impossible for a body to be the most noble of beings; for a body must be 
either animate or inanimate; and an animate body is manifestly nobler 
than any inanimate body. But an animate body is not animate precisely as 
body; otherwise all bodies would be animate. Therefore its animation 
depends upon some other thing, as our body depends for its animation on 
the soul. Hence that by which a body becomes animated must be nobler than 
the body. Therefore it is impossible that God should be a body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As we have said above (Q[1], A[9]), Holy Writ puts before 
us spiritual and divine things under the comparison of corporeal things. 
Hence, when it attributes to God the three dimensions under the 
comparison of corporeal quantity, it implies His virtual quantity; thus, 
by depth, it signifies His power of knowing hidden things; by height, the 
transcendence of His excelling power; by length, the duration of His 
existence; by breadth, His act of love for all. Or, as says Dionysius 
(Div. Nom. ix), by the depth of God is meant the incomprehensibility of 
His essence; by length, the procession of His all-pervading power; by 
breadth, His overspreading all things, inasmuch as all things lie under 
His protection.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Man is said to be after the image of God, not as regards 
his body, but as regards that whereby he excels other animals. Hence, 
when it is said, "Let us make man to our image and likeness", it is 
added, "And let him have dominion over the fishes  of the sea" (Gn. 
1:26). Now man excels all animals by his reason and intelligence; hence 
it is according to his intelligence and reason, which are incorporeal, 
that man is said to be according to the image of God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Corporeal parts are attributed to God in Scripture on 
account of His actions, and this is owing to a certain parallel. For 
instance the act of the eye is to see; hence the eye attributed to God 
signifies His power of seeing intellectually, not sensibly; and so on 
with the other parts.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Whatever pertains to posture, also, is only attributed to 
God by some sort of parallel. He is spoken of as sitting, on account of 
His unchangeableness and dominion; and as standing, on account of His 
power of overcoming whatever withstands Him.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 5: We draw near to God by no corporeal steps, since He is 
everywhere, but by the affections of our soul, and by the actions of that 
same soul do we withdraw from Him; thus, to draw near to or to withdraw 
signifies merely spiritual actions based on the metaphor of local motion.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is composed of matter and form?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is composed of matter and form. For whatever 
has a soul is composed of matter and form; since the soul is the form of 
the body. But Scripture attributes a soul to God; for it is mentioned in 
Hebrews (Heb. 10:38), where God says: "But My just man liveth by faith; 
but if he withdraw himself, he shall not please My soul." Therefore God 
is composed of matter and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, anger, joy and the like are passions of the composite. 
But these are attributed to God in Scripture: "The Lord was exceeding 
angry with His people" (Ps. 105:40). Therefore God is composed of matter 
and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, matter is the principle of individualization. But God 
seems to be individual, for He cannot be predicated of many. Therefore He 
is composed of matter and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Whatever is composed of matter and form is a body; for 
dimensive quantity is the first property of matter. But God is not a body 
as proved in the preceding Article; therefore He is not composed of 
matter and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, It is impossible that matter should exist in God. First, 
because matter is in potentiality. But we have shown (Q[2], A[3]) that 
God is pure act, without any potentiality. Hence it is impossible that 
God should be composed of matter and form. Secondly, because everything 
composed of matter and form owes its perfection and goodness to its form; 
therefore its goodness is participated, inasmuch as matter participates 
the form. Now the  first good and the best---viz. God---is not a 
participated good, because the essential good is prior to the 
participated good. Hence it is impossible that God should be composed of 
matter and form. Thirdly, because every agent acts by its form; hence the 
manner in which it has its form is the manner in which it is an agent. 
Therefore whatever is primarily and essentially an agent must be 
primarily and essentially form. Now God is the first agent, since He is 
the first efficient cause. He is therefore of His essence a form; and not 
composed of matter and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: A soul is attributed to God because His acts resemble the 
acts of a soul; for, that we will anything, is due to our soul. Hence 
what is pleasing to His will is said to be pleasing to His soul.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Anger and the like are attributed to God on account of a 
similitude of effect. Thus, because to punish is properly the act of an 
angry man, God's punishment is metaphorically spoken of as His anger.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Forms which can be received in matter are individualized by 
matter, which cannot be in another as in a subject since it is the first 
underlying subject; although form of itself, unless something else 
prevents it, can be received by many. But that form which cannot be 
received in matter, but is self-subsisting, is individualized precisely 
because it cannot be received in a subject; and such a form is God. Hence 
it does not follow that matter exists in God.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is the same as His essence or nature?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is not the same as His essence or nature. For 
nothing can be in itself. But the substance or nature of God---i.e. the 
Godhead---is said to be in God. Therefore it seems that God is not the 
same as His essence or nature.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, the effect is assimilated to its cause; for every agent 
produces its like. But in created things the "suppositum" is not 
identical with its nature; for a man is not the same as his humanity. 
Therefore God is not the same as His Godhead.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is said of God that He is life itself, and not only 
that He is a living thing: "I am the way, the truth, and the life" (Jn. 
14:6). Now the relation between Godhead and God is the same as the 
relation between life and a living thing. Therefore God is His very 
Godhead.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, God is the same as His essence or nature. To understand 
this, it must be noted that in things composed of matter and form, the 
nature or essence must differ from the "suppositum," because the essence 
or nature connotes only what is included in the definition of the 
species; as, humanity connotes all that is included in the definition of 
man, for it is by this that man is  man, and it is this that humanity 
signifies, that, namely, whereby man is man. Now individual matter, with 
all the individualizing accidents, is not included in the definition of 
the species. For this particular flesh, these bones, this blackness or 
whiteness, etc., are not included in the definition of a man. Therefore 
this flesh, these bones, and the accidental qualities distinguishing this 
particular matter, are not included in humanity; and yet they are 
included in the thing which is man. Hence the thing which is a man has 
something more in it than has humanity. Consequently humanity and a man 
are not wholly identical; but humanity is taken to mean the formal part 
of a man, because the principles whereby a thing is defined are regarded 
as the formal constituent in regard to the individualizing matter. On the 
other hand, in things not composed of matter and form, in which 
individualization is not due to individual matter---that is to say, to 
"this" matter---the very forms being individualized of themselves---it is 
necessary the forms themselves should be subsisting "supposita." 
Therefore "suppositum" and nature in them are identified. Since God then 
is not composed of matter and form, He must be His own Godhead, His own 
Life, and whatever else is thus predicated of Him.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: We can speak of simple things only as though they were like 
the composite things from which we derive our knowledge. Therefore in 
speaking of God, we use concrete nouns to signify His subsistence, 
because with us only those things subsist which are composite; and we use 
abstract nouns to signify His simplicity. In saying therefore that 
Godhead, or life, or the like are in God, we indicate the composite way 
in which our intellect understands, but not that there is any composition 
in God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The effects of God do not imitate Him perfectly, but only 
as far as they are able; and the imitation is here defective, precisely 
because what is simple and one, can only be represented by divers things; 
consequently, composition is accidental to them, and therefore, in them 
"suppositum" is not the same as nature.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether essence and existence are the same in God?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that essence and existence are not the same in God. For 
if it be so, then the divine being has nothing added to it. Now being to 
which no addition is made is universal being which is predicated of all 
things. Therefore it follows that God is being in general which can be 
predicated of everything. But this is false: "For men gave the 
incommunicable name to stones and wood" (Wis. 14:21). Therefore God's 
existence is not His essence.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, we can know "whether" God exists as said above (Q[2], 
A[2]); but we cannot know "what" He is. Therefore God's existence is not 
the same as His essence---that is, as His quiddity or nature.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Hilary says (Trin. vii): "In God existence is  not an 
accidental quality, but subsisting truth." Therefore what subsists in God 
is His existence.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, God is not only His own essence, as shown in the 
preceding article, but also His own existence. This may be shown in 
several ways. First, whatever a thing has besides its essence must be 
caused either by the constituent principles of that essence (like a 
property that necessarily accompanies the species---as the faculty of 
laughing is proper to a man---and is caused by the constituent principles 
of the species), or by some exterior agent---as heat is caused in water 
by fire. Therefore, if the existence of a thing differs from its essence, 
this existence must be caused either by some exterior agent or by its 
essential principles. Now it is impossible for a thing's existence to be 
caused by its essential constituent principles, for nothing can be the 
sufficient cause of its own existence, if its existence is caused. 
Therefore that thing, whose existence differs from its essence, must have 
its existence caused by another. But this cannot be true of God; because 
we call God the first efficient cause. Therefore it is impossible that in 
God His existence should differ from His essence. Secondly, existence is 
that which makes every form or nature actual; for goodness and humanity 
are spoken of as actual, only because they are spoken of as existing. 
Therefore existence must be compared to essence, if the latter is a 
distinct reality, as actuality to potentiality. Therefore, since in God 
there is no potentiality, as shown above (A[1]), it follows that in Him 
essence does not differ from existence. Therefore His essence is His 
existence. Thirdly, because, just as that which has fire, but is not 
itself fire, is on fire by participation; so that which has existence but 
is not existence, is a being by participation. But God is His own 
essence, as shown above (A[3]) if, therefore, He is not His own existence 
He will be not essential, but participated being. He will not therefore 
be the first being---which is absurd. Therefore God is His own existence, 
and not merely His own essence.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: A thing that has nothing added to it can be of two kinds. 
Either its essence precludes any addition; thus, for example, it is of 
the essence of an irrational animal to be without reason. Or we may 
understand a thing to have nothing added to it, inasmuch as its essence 
does not require that anything should be added to it; thus the genus 
animal is without reason, because it is not of the essence of animal in 
general to have reason; but neither is it to lack reason. And so the 
divine being has nothing added to it in the first sense; whereas 
universal being has nothing added to it in the second sense.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: "To be" can mean either of two things. It may mean the act 
of essence, or it may mean the composition of a proposition effected by 
the mind in joining a predicate to a subject. Taking "to be" in the first 
sense, we cannot understand God's existence nor His essence; but only in 
the second sense. We know that this proposition which we form about God 
when we say "God is," is true; and this we know from His effects (Q[2], 
A[2]).

 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is contained in a genus?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is contained in a genus. For a substance is a 
being that subsists of itself. But this is especially true of God. 
Therefore God is in a genus of substance.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, nothing can be measured save by something of its own 
genus; as length is measured by length and numbers by number. But God is 
the measure of all substances, as the Commentator shows (Metaph. x). 
Therefore God is in the genus of substance.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, In the mind, genus is prior to what it contains. But 
nothing is prior to God either really or mentally. Therefore God is not 
in any genus.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, A thing can be in a genus in two ways; either absolutely 
and properly, as a species contained under a genus; or as being reducible 
to it, as principles and privations. For example, a point and unity are 
reduced to the genus of quantity, as its principles; while blindness and 
all other privations are reduced to the genus of habit. But in neither 
way is God in a genus. That He cannot be a species of any genus may be 
shown in three ways. First, because a species is constituted of genus and 
difference. Now that from which the difference constituting the species 
is derived, is always related to that from which the genus is derived, as 
actuality is related to potentiality. For animal is derived from 
sensitive nature, by concretion as it were, for that is animal, which has 
a sensitive nature. Rational being, on the other hand, is derived from 
intellectual nature, because that is rational, which has an intellectual 
nature, and intelligence is compared to sense, as actuality is to 
potentiality. The same argument holds good in other things. Hence since 
in God actuality is not added to potentiality, it is impossible that He 
should be in any genus as a species. Secondly, since the existence of God 
is His essence, if God were in any genus, He would be the genus "being", 
because, since genus is predicated as an essential it refers to the 
essence of a thing. But the Philosopher has shown (Metaph. iii) that 
being cannot be a genus, for every genus has differences distinct from 
its generic essence. Now no difference can exist distinct from being; for 
non-being cannot be a difference. It follows then that God is not in a 
genus. Thirdly, because all in one genus agree in the quiddity or essence 
of the genus which is predicated of them as an essential, but they differ 
in their existence. For the existence of man and of horse is not the 
same; as also of this man and that man: thus in every member of a genus, 
existence and quiddity---i.e. essence---must differ. But in God they do 
not differ, as shown in the preceding article. Therefore it is plain that 
God is not in a genus as if He were a species. From this it is also plain 
that He has no genus nor difference, nor can there be any definition of 
Him; nor, save through His effects, a demonstration of Him: for a 
definition is from genus and difference; and the mean of a demonstration 
is a definition. That  God is not in a genus, as reducible to it as its 
principle, is clear from this, that a principle reducible to any genus 
does not extend beyond that genus; as, a point is the principle of 
continuous quantity alone; and unity, of discontinuous quantity. But God 
is the principle of all being. Therefore He is not contained in any genus 
as its principle.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The word substance signifies not only what exists of 
itself---for existence cannot of itself be a genus, as shown in the body 
of the article; but, it also signifies an essence that has the property 
of existing in this way---namely, of existing of itself; this existence, 
however, is not its essence. Thus it is clear that God is not in the 
genus of substance.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: This objection turns upon proportionate measure which must 
be homogeneous with what is measured. Now, God is not a measure 
proportionate to anything. Still, He is called the measure of all things, 
in the sense that everything has being only according as it resembles Him.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether in God there are any accidents?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that there are accidents in God. For substance cannot be 
an accident, as Aristotle says (Phys. i). Therefore that which is an 
accident in one, cannot, in another, be a substance. Thus it is proved 
that heat cannot be the substantial form of fire, because it is an 
accident in other things. But wisdom, virtue, and the like, which are 
accidents in us, are attributes of God. Therefore in God there are 
accidents.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, in every genus there is a first principle. But there are 
many "genera" of accidents. If, therefore, the primal members of these 
genera are not in God, there will be many primal beings other than 
God---which is absurd.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Every accident is in a subject. But God cannot be a 
subject, for "no simple form can be a subject", as Boethius says (De 
Trin.). Therefore in God there cannot be any accident.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, From all we have said, it is clear there can be no 
accident in God. First, because a subject is compared to its accidents as 
potentiality to actuality; for a subject is in some sense made actual by 
its accidents. But there can be no potentiality in God, as was shown 
(Q[2], A[3]). Secondly, because God is His own existence; and as Boethius 
says (Hebdom.), although every essence may have something superadded to 
it, this cannot apply to absolute being: thus a heated substance can have 
something extraneous to heat added to it, as whiteness, nevertheless 
absolute heat can have nothing else than heat. Thirdly, because what is 
essential is prior to what is accidental. Whence as God is absolute 
primal being, there can be in Him nothing accidental. Neither can He have 
any essential accidents (as the capability of laughing is  an essential 
accident of man), because such accidents are caused by the constituent 
principles of the subject. Now there can be nothing caused in God, since 
He is the first cause. Hence it follows that there is no accident in God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Virtue and wisdom are not predicated of God and of us 
univocally. Hence it does not follow that there are accidents in God as 
there are in us.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Since substance is prior to its accidents, the principles 
of accidents are reducible to the principles of the substance as to that 
which is prior; although God is not first as if contained in the genus of 
substance; yet He is first in respect to all being, outside of every 
genus.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is altogether simple?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is not altogether simple. For whatever is from 
God must imitate Him. Thus from the first being are all beings; and from 
the first good is all good. But in the things which God has made, nothing 
is altogether simple. Therefore neither is God altogether simple.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, whatever is best must be attributed to God. But with us 
that which is composite is better than that which is simple; thus, 
chemical compounds are better than simple elements, and animals than the 
parts that compose them. Therefore it cannot be said that God is 
altogether simple.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. iv, 6,7): "God is truly and 
absolutely simple."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, The absolute simplicity of God may be shown in many ways. 
First, from the previous articles of this question. For there is neither 
composition of quantitative parts in God, since He is not a body; nor 
composition of matter and form; nor does His nature differ from His 
"suppositum"; nor His essence from His existence; neither is there in Him 
composition of genus and difference, nor of subject and accident. 
Therefore, it is clear that God is nowise composite, but is altogether 
simple. Secondly, because every composite is posterior to its component 
parts, and is dependent on them; but God is the first being, as shown 
above (Q[2], A[3]). Thirdly, because every composite has a cause, for 
things in themselves different cannot unite unless something causes them 
to unite. But God is uncaused, as shown above (Q[2], A[3]), since He is 
the first efficient cause. Fourthly, because in every composite there 
must be potentiality and actuality; but this does not apply to God; for 
either one of the parts actuates another, or at least all the parts are 
potential to the whole. Fifthly, because nothing composite can be 
predicated of any single one of its parts. And this is evident in a whole 
made up of dissimilar parts; for no part of a man is a man, nor any of 
the parts of the foot, a foot. But in wholes made up of similar parts, 
although something which is  predicated of the whole may be predicated of 
a part (as a part of the air is air, and a part of water, water), 
nevertheless certain things are predicable of the whole which cannot be 
predicated of any of the parts; for instance, if the whole volume of 
water is two cubits, no part of it can be two cubits. Thus in every 
composite there is something which is not it itself. But, even if this 
could be said of whatever has a form, viz. that it has something which is 
not it itself, as in a white object there is something which does not 
belong to the essence of white; nevertheless in the form itself, there is 
nothing besides itself. And so, since God is absolute form, or rather 
absolute being, He can be in no way composite. Hilary implies this 
argument, when he says (De Trin. vii): "God, Who is strength, is not made 
up of things that are weak; nor is He Who is light, composed of things 
that are dim."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Whatever is from God imitates Him, as caused things imitate 
the first cause. But it is of the essence of a thing to be in some sort 
composite; because at least its existence differs from its essence, as 
will be shown hereafter, (Q[4], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: With us composite things are better than simple things, 
because the perfections of created goodness cannot be found in one simple 
thing, but in many things. But the perfection of divine goodness is found 
in one simple thing (Q[4], A[1] and Q[6], A[2]).


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God enters into the composition of other things?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God enters into the composition of other things, 
for Dionysius says (Coel. Hier. iv): "The being of all things is that 
which is above being---the Godhead." But the being of all things enters 
into the composition of everything. Therefore God enters into the 
composition of other things.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, God is a form; for Augustine says (De Verb. Dom., 
[*Serm. xxxviii]) that, "the word of God, which is God, is an uncreated 
form." But a form is part of a compound. Therefore God is part of some 
compound.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, whatever things exist, in no way differing from each 
other, are the same. But God and primary matter exist, and in no way 
differ from each other. Therefore they are absolutely the same. But 
primary matter enters into the composition things. Therefore also does 
God. Proof of the minor---whatever things differ, they differ by some 
differences, and therefore must be composite. But God and primary matter 
are altogether simple. Therefore they nowise differ from each other.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] OTC Para. 1/2

 On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ii): "There can be no 
touching Him," i.e. God, "nor any other union with Him by mingling part 
with part."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] OTC Para. 2/2

 Further, the first cause rules all things without commingling with them, 
as the Philosopher says (De Causis). 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, On this point there have been three errors. Some have 
affirmed that God is the world-soul, as is clear from Augustine (De Civ. 
Dei vii, 6). This is practically the same as the opinion of those who 
assert that God is the soul of the highest heaven. Again, others have 
said that God is the formal principle of all things; and this was the 
theory of the Almaricians. The third error is that of David of Dinant, 
who most absurdly taught that God was primary matter. Now all these 
contain manifest untruth; since it is not possible for God to enter into 
the composition of anything, either as a formal or a material principle. 
First, because God is the first efficient cause. Now the efficient cause 
is not identical numerically with the form of the thing caused, but only 
specifically: for man begets man. But primary matter can be neither 
numerically nor specifically identical with an efficient cause; for the 
former is merely potential, while the latter is actual. Secondly, 
because, since God is the first efficient cause, to act belongs to Him 
primarily and essentially. But that which enters into composition with 
anything does not act primarily and essentially, but rather the composite 
so acts; for the hand does not act, but the man by his hand; and, fire 
warms by its heat. Hence God cannot be part of a compound. Thirdly, 
because no part of a compound can be absolutely primal among beings---not 
even matter, nor form, though they are the primal parts of every 
compound. For matter is merely potential; and potentiality is absolutely 
posterior to actuality, as is clear from the foregoing (Q[3], A[1]): 
while a form which is part of a compound is a participated form; and as 
that which participates is posterior to that which is essential, so 
likewise is that which is participated; as fire in ignited objects is 
posterior to fire that is essentially such. Now it has been proved that 
God is absolutely primal being (Q[2], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The Godhead is called the being of all things, as their 
efficient and exemplar cause, but not as being their essence.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The Word is an exemplar form; but not a form that is part 
of a compound.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[3] A[8] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Simple things do not differ by added differences---for this 
is the property of compounds. Thus man and horse differ by their 
differences, rational and irrational; which differences, however, do not 
differ from each other by other differences. Hence, to be quite accurate, 
it is better to say that they are, not different, but diverse. Hence, 
according to the Philosopher (Metaph. x), "things which are diverse are 
absolutely distinct, but things which are different differ by something." 
Therefore, strictly speaking, primary matter and God do not differ, but 
are by their very being, diverse. Hence it does not follow they are the 
same.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] Out. Para. 1/2

THE PERFECTION OF GOD (THREE ARTICLES)

 Having considered the divine simplicity, we treat next of God's 
perfection. Now because everything in so far as it is perfect  is called 
good, we shall speak first of the divine perfection; secondly of the 
divine goodness.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] Out. Para. 2/2

 Concerning the first there are three points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether God is perfect?

 (2) Whether God is perfect universally, as having in Himself the 
perfections of all things?

 (3) Whether creatures can be said to be like God?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is perfect?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that perfection does not belong to God. For we say a 
thing is perfect if it is completely made. But it does not befit God to 
be made. Therefore He is not perfect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, God is the first beginning of things. But the beginnings 
of things seem to be imperfect, as seed is the beginning of animal and 
vegetable life. Therefore God is imperfect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, as shown above (Q[3], A[4]), God's essence is existence. 
But existence seems most imperfect, since it is most universal and 
receptive of all modification. Therefore God is imperfect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written: "Be you perfect as also your heavenly 
Father is perfect" (Mt. 5:48).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, As the Philosopher relates (Metaph. xii), some ancient 
philosophers, namely, the Pythagoreans and Leucippus, did not predicate 
"best" and "most perfect" of the first principle. The reason was that the 
ancient philosophers considered only a material principle; and a material 
principle is most imperfect. For since matter as such is merely 
potential, the first material principle must be simply potential, and 
thus most imperfect. Now God is the first principle, not material, but in 
the order of efficient cause, which must be most perfect. For just as 
matter, as such, is merely potential, an agent, as such, is in the state 
of actuality. Hence, the first active principle must needs be most 
actual, and therefore most perfect; for a thing is perfect in proportion 
to its state of actuality, because we call that perfect which lacks 
nothing of the mode of its perfection.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As Gregory says (Moral. v, 26,29): "Though our lips can 
only stammer, we yet chant the high things of God." For that which is not 
made is improperly called perfect. Nevertheless because created things 
are then called perfect, when from potentiality they are brought into 
actuality, this word "perfect" signifies whatever is not wanting in 
actuality, whether this be by way of perfection or not.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The material principle which with us is found to be 
imperfect, cannot be absolutely primal; but must be preceded by something 
perfect. For seed, though it be the principle of animal  life reproduced 
through seed, has previous to it, the animal or plant from which is came. 
Because, previous to that which is potential, must be that which is 
actual; since a potential being can only be reduced into act by some 
being already actual.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Existence is the most perfect of all things, for it is 
compared to all things as that by which they are made actual; for nothing 
has actuality except so far as it exists. Hence existence is that which 
actuates all things, even their forms. Therefore it is not compared to 
other things as the receiver is to the received; but rather as the 
received to the receiver. When therefore I speak of the existence of man, 
or horse, or anything else, existence is considered a formal principle, 
and as something received; and not as that which exists.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether the perfections of all things are in God?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that the perfections of all things are not in God. For 
God is simple, as shown above (Q[3], A[7]); whereas the perfections of 
things are many and diverse. Therefore the perfections of all things are 
not in God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, opposites cannot coexist. Now the perfections of things 
are opposed to each other, for each thing is perfected by its specific 
difference. But the differences by which "genera" are divided, and 
"species" constituted, are opposed to each other. Therefore because 
opposites cannot coexist in the same subject, it seems that the 
perfections of all things are not in God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, a living thing is more perfect than what merely exists; 
and an intelligent thing than what merely lives. Therefore life is more 
perfect than existence; and knowledge than life. But the essence of God 
is existence itself. Therefore He has not the perfections of life, and 
knowledge, and other similar perfections.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. v) that "God in His one 
existence prepossesses all things."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, All created perfections are in God. Hence He is spoken of 
as universally perfect, because He lacks not (says the Commentator, 
Metaph. v) any excellence which may be found in any genus. This may be 
seen from two considerations. First, because whatever perfection exists 
in an effect must be found in the effective cause: either in the same 
formality, if it is a univocal agent---as when man reproduces man; or in 
a more eminent degree, if it is an equivocal agent---thus in the sun is 
the likeness of whatever is generated by the sun's power. Now it is plain 
that the effect pre-exists virtually in the efficient cause: and although 
to pre-exist in the potentiality of a material cause is to pre-exist in a 
more imperfect way, since matter as such is imperfect, and an agent as 
such is perfect; still to pre-exist virtually in the efficient cause is 
to pre-exist not in a more imperfect, but in a  more perfect way. Since 
therefore God is the first effective cause of things, the perfections of 
all things must pre-exist in God in a more eminent way. Dionysius implies 
the same line of argument by saying of God (Div. Nom. v): "It is not that 
He is this and not that, but that He is all, as the cause of all." 
Secondly, from what has been already proved, God is existence itself, of 
itself subsistent (Q[3], A[4]). Consequently, He must contain within 
Himself the whole perfection of being. For it is clear that if some hot 
thing has not the whole perfection of heat, this is because heat is not 
participated in its full perfection; but if this heat were 
self-subsisting, nothing of the virtue of heat would be wanting to it. 
Since therefore God is subsisting being itself, nothing of the perfection 
of being can be wanting to Him. Now all created perfections are included 
in the perfection of being; for things are perfect, precisely so far as 
they have being after some fashion. It follows therefore that the 
perfection of no one thing is wanting to God. This line of argument, too, 
is implied by Dionysius (Div. Nom. v), when he says that, "God exists not 
in any single mode, but embraces all being within Himself, absolutely, 
without limitation, uniformly;" and afterwards he adds that, "He is the 
very existence to subsisting things."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Even as the sun (as Dionysius remarks, (Div. Nom. v)), 
while remaining one and shining uniformly, contains within itself first 
and uniformly the substances of sensible things, and many and diverse 
qualities; "a fortiori" should all things in a kind of natural unity 
pre-exist in the cause of all things; and thus things diverse and in 
themselves opposed to each other, pre-exist in God as one, without injury 
to His simplicity. This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The same Dionysius says (Div. Nom. v) that, although 
existence is more perfect than life, and life than wisdom, if they are 
considered as distinguished in idea; nevertheless, a living thing is more 
perfect than what merely exists, because living things also exist and 
intelligent things both exist and live. Although therefore existence does 
not include life and wisdom, because that which participates in existence 
need not participate in every mode of existence; nevertheless God's 
existence includes in itself life and wisdom, because nothing of the 
perfection of being can be wanting to Him who is subsisting being itself.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether any creature can be like God?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that no creature can be like God. For it is written (Ps. 
85:8): "There is none among the gods like unto Thee, O Lord." But of all 
creatures the most excellent are those which are called participation 
gods. Therefore still less can other creatures be said to be like God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, likeness implies comparison. But there can be no 
comparison between things in a different "genus." Therefore  neither can 
there be any likeness. Thus we do not say that sweetness is like 
whiteness. But no creature is in the same "genus" as God: since God is no 
"genus," as shown above (Q[3], A[5]). Therefore no creature is like God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, we speak of those things as like which agree in form. 
But nothing can agree with God in form; for, save in God alone, essence 
and existence differ. Therefore no creature can be like to God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, among like things there is mutual likeness; for like is 
like to like. If therefore any creature is like God, God will be like 
some creature, which is against what is said by Isaias: "To whom have you 
likened God?" (Is. 40:18).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written: "Let us make man to our image and 
likeness" (Gn. 1:26), and: "When He shall appear we shall be like to Him" 
(1 Jn. 3:2).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Since likeness is based upon agreement or communication 
in form, it varies according to the many modes of communication in form. 
Some things are said to be like, which communicate in the same form 
according to the same formality, and according to the same mode; and 
these are said to be not merely like, but equal in their likeness; as two 
things equally white are said to be alike in whiteness; and this is the 
most perfect likeness. In another way, we speak of things as alike which 
communicate in form according to the same formality, though not according 
to the same measure, but according to more or less, as something less 
white is said to be like another thing more white; and this is imperfect 
likeness. In a third way some things are said to be alike which 
communicate in the same form, but not according to the same formality; as 
we see in non-univocal agents. For since every agent reproduces itself so 
far as it is an agent, and everything acts according to the manner of its 
form, the effect must in some way resemble the form of the agent. If 
therefore the agent is contained in the same species as its effect, there 
will be a likeness in form between that which makes and that which is 
made, according to the same formality of the species; as man reproduces 
man. If, however, the agent and its effect are not contained in the same 
species, there will be a likeness, but not according to the formality of 
the same species; as things generated by the sun's heat may be in some 
sort spoken of as like the sun, not as though they received the form of 
the sun in its specific likeness, but in its generic likeness. Therefore 
if there is an agent not contained in any "genus," its effect will still 
more distantly reproduce the form of the agent, not, that is, so as to 
participate in the likeness of the agent's form according to the same 
specific or generic formality, but only according to some sort of 
analogy; as existence is common to all. In this way all created things, 
so far as they are beings, are like God as the first and universal 
principle of all being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: As Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ix), when Holy Writ  declares 
that nothing is like God, it does not mean to deny all likeness to Him. 
For, "the same things can be like and unlike to God: like, according as 
they imitate Him, as far as He, Who is not perfectly imitable, can be 
imitated; unlike according as they fall short of their cause," not merely 
in intensity and remission, as that which is less white falls short of 
that which is more white; but because they are not in agreement, 
specifically or generically.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: God is not related to creatures as though belonging to a 
different "genus," but as transcending every "genus," and as the 
principle of all "genera."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Likeness of creatures to God is not affirmed on account of 
agreement in form according to the formality of the same genus or 
species, but solely according to analogy, inasmuch as God is essential 
being, whereas other things are beings by participation.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Although it may be admitted that creatures are in some sort 
like God, it must nowise be admitted that God is like creatures; because, 
as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ix): "A mutual likeness may be found between 
things of the same order, but not between a cause and that which is 
caused." For, we say that a statue is like a man, but not conversely; so 
also a creature can be spoken of as in some sort like God; but not that 
God is like a creature.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] Out. Para. 1/2

OF GOODNESS IN GENERAL (SIX ARTICLES)

 We next consider goodness: First, goodness in general. Secondly, the 
goodness of God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] Out. Para. 2/2

 Under the first head there are six points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether goodness and being are the same really?

 (2) Granted that they differ only in idea, which is prior in thought?

 (3) Granted that being is prior, whether every being is good?

 (4) To what cause should goodness be reduced?

 (5) Whether goodness consists in mode, species, and order?

 (6) Whether goodness is divided into the virtuous, the useful, and the 
pleasant?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether goodness differs really from being?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that goodness differs really from being. For Boethius 
says (De Hebdom.): "I perceive that in nature the fact that things are 
good is one thing: that they are is another." Therefore goodness and 
being really differ.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, nothing can be its own form. "But that is called good 
which has the form of being", according to the commentary on De Causis. 
Therefore goodness differs really from being. 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, goodness can be more or less. But being cannot be more 
or less. Therefore goodness differs really from being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Doctr. Christ. i, 42) that, 
"inasmuch as we exist we are good."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Goodness and being are really the same, and differ only 
in idea; which is clear from the following argument. The essence of 
goodness consists in this, that it is in some way desirable. Hence the 
Philosopher says (Ethic. i): "Goodness is what all desire." Now it is 
clear that a thing is desirable only in so far as it is perfect; for all 
desire their own perfection. But everything is perfect so far as it is 
actual. Therefore it is clear that a thing is perfect so far as it 
exists; for it is existence that makes all things actual, as is clear 
from the foregoing (Q[3], A[4]; Q[4], A[1]). Hence it is clear that 
goodness and being are the same really. But goodness presents the aspect 
of desirableness, which being does not present.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Although goodness and being are the same really, 
nevertheless since they differ in thought, they are not predicated of a 
thing absolutely in the same way. Since being properly signifies that 
something actually is, and actuality properly correlates to potentiality; 
a thing is, in consequence, said simply to have being, accordingly as it 
is primarily distinguished from that which is only in potentiality; and 
this is precisely each thing's substantial being. Hence by its 
substantial being, everything is said to have being simply; but by any 
further actuality it is said to have being relatively. Thus to be white 
implies relative being, for to be white does not take a thing out of 
simply potential being; because only a thing that actually has being can 
receive this mode of being. But goodness signifies perfection which is 
desirable; and consequently of ultimate perfection. Hence that which has 
ultimate perfection is said to be simply good; but that which has not the 
ultimate perfection it ought to have (although, in so far as it is at all 
actual, it has some perfection), is not said to be perfect simply nor 
good simply, but only relatively. In this way, therefore, viewed in its 
primal (i.e. substantial) being a thing is said to be simply, and to be 
good relatively (i.e. in so far as it has being) but viewed in its 
complete actuality, a thing is said to be relatively, and to be good 
simply. Hence the saying of Boethius (De Hebrom.), "I perceive that in 
nature the fact that things are good is one thing; that they are is 
another," is to be referred to a thing's goodness simply, and having 
being simply. Because, regarded in its primal actuality, a thing simply 
exists; and regarded in its complete actuality, it is good simply---in 
such sort that even in its primal actuality, it is in some sort good, and 
even in its complete actuality, it in some sort has being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Goodness is a form so far as absolute goodness signifies 
complete actuality.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1 

 Reply OBJ 3: Again, goodness is spoken of as more or less according to a 
thing's superadded actuality, for example, as to knowledge or virtue.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether goodness is prior in idea to being?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that goodness is prior in idea to being. For names are 
arranged according to the arrangement of the things signified by the 
names. But Dionysius (Div. Nom. iii) assigned the first place, amongst 
the other names of God, to His goodness rather than to His being. 
Therefore in idea goodness is prior to being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, that which is the more extensive is prior in idea. But 
goodness is more extensive than being, because, as Dionysius notes (Div. 
Nom. v), "goodness extends to things both existing and non-existing; 
whereas existence extends to existing things alone." Therefore goodness 
is in idea prior to being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, what is the more universal is prior in idea. But 
goodness seems to be more universal than being, since goodness has the 
aspect of desirable; whereas to some non-existence is desirable; for it 
is said of Judas: "It were better for him, if that man had not been born" 
(Mt. 26:24). Therefore in idea goodness is prior to being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, not only is existence desirable, but life, knowledge, 
and many other things besides. Thus it seems that existence is a 
particular appetible, and goodness a universal appetible. Therefore, 
absolutely, goodness is prior in idea to being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is said by Aristotle (De Causis) that "the first of 
created things is being."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, In idea being is prior to goodness. For the meaning 
signified by the name of a thing is that which the mind conceives of the 
thing and intends by the word that stands for it. Therefore, that is 
prior in idea, which is first conceived by the intellect. Now the first 
thing conceived by the intellect is being; because everything is knowable 
only inasmuch as it is in actuality. Hence, being is the proper object of 
the intellect, and is primarily intelligible; as sound is that which is 
primarily audible. Therefore in idea being is prior to goodness.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Dionysius discusses the Divine Names (Div. Nom. i, iii) as 
implying some causal relation in God; for we name God, as he says, from 
creatures, as a cause from its effects. But goodness, since it has the 
aspect of desirable, implies the idea of a final cause, the causality of 
which is first among causes, since an agent does not act except for some 
end; and by an agent matter is moved to its form. Hence the end is called 
the cause of causes. Thus goodness, as a cause, is prior to being, as is 
the end to the form. Therefore among the names signifying the divine 
causality,  goodness precedes being. Again, according to the Platonists, 
who, through not distinguishing primary matter from privation, said that 
matter was non-being, goodness is more extensively participated than 
being; for primary matter participates in goodness as tending to it, for 
all seek their like; but it does not participate in being, since it is 
presumed to be non-being. Therefore Dionysius says that "goodness extends 
to non-existence" (Div. Nom. v).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The same solution is applied to this objection. Or it may 
be said that goodness extends to existing and non-existing things, not so 
far as it can be predicated of them, but so far as it can cause 
them---if, indeed, by non-existence we understand not simply those things 
which do not exist, but those which are potential, and not actual. For 
goodness has the aspect of the end, in which not only actual things find 
their completion, but also towards which tend even those things which are 
not actual, but merely potential. Now being implies the habitude of a 
formal cause only, either inherent or exemplar; and its causality does 
not extend save to those things which are actual.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Non-being is desirable, not of itself, but only 
relatively---i.e. inasmuch as the removal of an evil, which can only be 
removed by non-being, is desirable. Now the removal of an evil cannot be 
desirable, except so far as this evil deprives a thing of some being. 
Therefore being is desirable of itself; and non-being only relatively, 
inasmuch as one seeks some mode of being of which one cannot bear to be 
deprived; thus even non-being can be spoken of as relatively good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Life, wisdom, and the like, are desirable only so far as 
they are actual. Hence, in each one of them some sort of being is 
desired. And thus nothing can be desired except being; and consequently 
nothing is good except being.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether every being is good?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that not every being is good. For goodness is something 
superadded to being, as is clear from A[1]. But whatever is added to 
being limits it; as substance, quantity, quality, etc. Therefore goodness 
limits being. Therefore not every being is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, no evil is good: "Woe to you that call evil good and 
good evil" (Is. 5:20). But some things are called evil. Therefore not 
every being is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, goodness implies desirability. Now primary matter does 
not imply desirability, but rather that which desires. Therefore primary 
matter does not contain the formality of goodness. Therefore not every 
being is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, the Philosopher notes (Metaph. iii) that "in mathematics 
goodness does not exist." But mathematics are entities; otherwise there 
would be no science of mathematics. Therefore not  every being is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Every being that is not God is God's creature. Now 
every creature of God is good (1 Tim. 4:4): and God is the greatest good. 
Therefore every being is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Every being, as being, is good. For all being, as being, 
has actuality and is in some way perfect; since every act implies some 
sort of perfection; and perfection implies desirability and goodness, as 
is clear from A[1]. Hence it follows that every being as such is good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Substance, quantity, quality, and everything included in 
them, limit being by applying it to some essence or nature. Now in this 
sense, goodness does not add anything to being beyond the aspect of 
desirability and perfection, which is also proper to being, whatever kind 
of nature it may be. Hence goodness does not limit being.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: No being can be spoken of as evil, formally as being, but 
only so far as it lacks being. Thus a man is said to be evil, because he 
lacks some virtue; and an eye is said to be evil, because it lacks the 
power to see well.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: As primary matter has only potential being, so it is only 
potentially good. Although, according to the Platonists, primary matter 
may be said to be a non-being on account of the privation attaching to 
it, nevertheless, it does participate to a certain extent in goodness, 
viz. by its relation to, or aptitude for, goodness. Consequently, to be 
desirable is not its property, but to desire.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Mathematical entities do not subsist as realities; because 
they would be in some sort good if they subsisted; but they have only 
logical existence, inasmuch as they are abstracted from motion and 
matter; thus they cannot have the aspect of an end, which itself has the 
aspect of moving another. Nor is it repugnant that there should be in 
some logical entity neither goodness nor form of goodness; since the idea 
of being is prior to the idea of goodness, as was said in the preceding 
article.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether goodness has the aspect of a final cause?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that goodness has not the aspect of a final cause, but 
rather of the other causes. For, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv), 
"Goodness is praised as beauty." But beauty has the aspect of a formal 
cause. Therefore goodness has the aspect of a formal cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, goodness is self-diffusive; for Dionysius says (Div. 
Nom. iv) that goodness is that whereby all things subsist, and are. But 
to be self-giving implies the aspect of an efficient  cause. Therefore 
goodness has the aspect of an efficient cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, Augustine says (De Doctr. Christ. i, 31) that "we exist 
because God is good." But we owe our existence to God as the efficient 
cause. Therefore goodness implies the aspect of an efficient cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Phys. ii) that "that is to be 
considered as the end and the good of other things, for the sake of which 
something is." Therefore goodness has the aspect of a final cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Since goodness is that which all things desire, and since 
this has the aspect of an end, it is clear that goodness implies the 
aspect of an end. Nevertheless, the idea of goodness presupposes the idea 
of an efficient cause, and also of a formal cause. For we see that what 
is first in causing, is last in the thing caused. Fire, e.g. heats first 
of all before it reproduces the form of fire; though the heat in the fire 
follows from its substantial form. Now in causing, goodness and the end 
come first, both of which move the agent to act; secondly, the action of 
the agent moving to the form; thirdly, comes the form. Hence in that 
which is caused the converse ought to take place, so that there should be 
first, the form whereby it is a being; secondly, we consider in it its 
effective power, whereby it is perfect in being, for a thing is perfect 
when it can reproduce its like, as the Philosopher says (Meteor. iv); 
thirdly, there follows the formality of goodness which is the basic 
principle of its perfection.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Beauty and goodness in a thing are identical fundamentally; 
for they are based upon the same thing, namely, the form; and 
consequently goodness is praised as beauty. But they differ logically, 
for goodness properly relates to the appetite (goodness being what all 
things desire); and therefore it has the aspect of an end (the appetite 
being a kind of movement towards a thing). On the other hand, beauty 
relates to the cognitive faculty; for beautiful things are those which 
please when seen. Hence beauty consists in due proportion; for the senses 
delight in things duly proportioned, as in what is after their own 
kind---because even sense is a sort of reason, just as is every cognitive 
faculty. Now since knowledge is by assimilation, and similarity relates 
to form, beauty properly belongs to the nature of a formal cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Goodness is described as self-diffusive in the sense that 
an end is said to move.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: He who has a will is said to be good, so far as he has a 
good will; because it is by our will that we employ whatever powers we 
may have. Hence a man is said to be good, not by his good understanding; 
but by his good will. Now the will relates to the end as to its proper 
object. Thus the saying, "we exist because God is good" has reference to 
the final cause.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1 

Whether the essence of goodness consists in mode, species and order?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that the essence of goodness does not consist in mode, 
species and order. For goodness and being differ logically. But mode, 
species and order seem to belong to the nature of being, for it is 
written: "Thou hast ordered all things in measure, and number, and 
weight" (Wis. 11:21). And to these three can be reduced species, mode and 
order, as Augustine says (Gen. ad lit. iv, 3): "Measure fixes the mode of 
everything, number gives it its species, and weight gives it rest and 
stability." Therefore the essence of goodness does not consist in mode, 
species and order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, mode, species and order are themselves good. Therefore 
if the essence of goodness consists in mode, species and order, then 
every mode must have its own mode, species and order. The same would be 
the case with species and order in endless succession.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, evil is the privation of mode, species and order. But 
evil is not the total absence of goodness. Therefore the essence of 
goodness does not consist in mode, species and order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, that wherein consists the essence of goodness cannot be 
spoken of as evil. Yet we can speak of an evil mode, species and order. 
Therefore the essence of goodness does not consist in mode, species and 
order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 5: Further, mode, species and order are caused by weight, number and 
measure, as appears from the quotation from Augustine. But not every good 
thing has weight, number and measure; for Ambrose says (Hexam. i, 9): "It 
is of the nature of light not to have been created in number, weight and 
measure." Therefore the essence of goodness does not consist in mode, 
species and order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Nat. Boni. iii): "These 
three---mode, species and order---as common good things, are in 
everything God has made; thus, where these three abound the things are 
very good; where they are less, the things are less good; where they do 
not exist at all, there can be nothing good." But this would not be 
unless the essence of goodness consisted in them. Therefore the essence 
of goodness consists in mode, species and order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Everything is said to be good so far as it is perfect; 
for in that way only is it desirable (as shown above AA[1],3). Now a 
thing is said to be perfect if it lacks nothing according to the mode of 
its perfection. But since everything is what it is by its form (and since 
the form presupposes certain things, and from the form certain things 
necessarily follow), in order for a thing to be perfect and good it must 
have a form, together with all that precedes and follows upon that form. 
Now the form presupposes determination or commensuration of its 
principles, whether material or efficient, and this is signified by the 
mode:  hence it is said that the measure marks the mode. But the form 
itself is signified by the species; for everything is placed in its 
species by its form. Hence the number is said to give the species, for 
definitions signifying species are like numbers, according to the 
Philosopher (Metaph. x); for as a unit added to, or taken from a number, 
changes its species, so a difference added to, or taken from a 
definition, changes its species. Further, upon the form follows an 
inclination to the end, or to an action, or something of the sort; for 
everything, in so far as it is in act, acts and tends towards that which 
is in accordance with its form; and this belongs to weight and order. 
Hence the essence of goodness, so far as it consists in perfection, 
consists also in mode, species and order.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: These three only follow upon being, so far as it is 
perfect, and according to this perfection is it good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Mode, species and order are said to be good, and to be 
beings, not as though they themselves were subsistences, but because it 
is through them that other things are both beings and good. Hence they 
have no need of other things whereby they are good: for they are spoken 
of as good, not as though formally constituted so by something else, but 
as formally constituting others good: thus whiteness is not said to be a 
being as though it were by anything else; but because, by it, something 
else has accidental being, as an object that is white.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Every being is due to some form. Hence, according to every 
being of a thing is its mode, species, order. Thus, a man has a mode, 
species and order as he is white, virtuous, learned and so on; according 
to everything predicated of him. But evil deprives a thing of some sort 
of being, as blindness deprives us of that being which is sight; yet it 
does not destroy every mode, species and order, but only such as follow 
upon the being of sight.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Augustine says (De Nat. Boni. xxiii), "Every mode, as mode, 
is good" (and the same can be said of species and order). "But an evil 
mode, species and order are so called as being less than they ought to 
be, or as not belonging to that which they ought to belong. Therefore 
they are called evil, because they are out of place and incongruous."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[5] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 5: The nature of light is spoken of as being without number, 
weight and measure, not absolutely, but in comparison with corporeal 
things, because the power of light extends to all corporeal things; 
inasmuch as it is an active quality of the first body that causes change, 
i.e. the heavens.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether goodness is rightly divided into the virtuous*, the useful and 
the pleasant? [*"Bonum honestum" is the virtuous good considered as 
fitting. (cf. SS, Q[141], A[3]; SS, Q[145])]

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that goodness is not rightly divided into the virtuous, 
the useful and the pleasant. For goodness is divided by  the ten 
predicaments, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. i). But the virtuous, the 
useful and the pleasant can be found under one predicament. Therefore 
goodness is not rightly divided by them.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, every division is made by opposites. But these three do 
not seem to be opposites; for the virtuous is pleasing, and no wickedness 
is useful; whereas this ought to be the case if the division were made by 
opposites, for then the virtuous and the useful would be opposed; and 
Tully speaks of this (De Offic. ii). Therefore this division is incorrect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, where one thing is on account of another, there is only 
one thing. But the useful is not goodness, except so far as it is 
pleasing and virtuous. Therefore the useful ought not to divided against 
the pleasant and the virtuous.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Ambrose makes use of this division of goodness (De 
Offic. i, 9)

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, This division properly concerns human goodness. But if we 
consider the nature of goodness from a higher and more universal point of 
view, we shall find that this division properly concerns goodness as 
such. For everything is good so far as it is desirable, and is a term of 
the movement of the appetite; the term of whose movement can be seen from 
a consideration of the movement of a natural body. Now the movement of a 
natural body is terminated by the end absolutely; and relatively by the 
means through which it comes to the end, where the movement ceases; so a 
thing is called a term of movement, so far as it terminates any part of 
that movement. Now the ultimate term of movement can be taken in two 
ways, either as the thing itself towards which it tends, e.g. a place or 
form; or a state of rest in that thing. Thus, in the movement of the 
appetite, the thing desired that terminates the movement of the appetite 
relatively, as a means by which something tends towards another, is 
called the useful; but that sought after as the last thing absolutely 
terminating the movement of the appetite, as a thing towards which for 
its own sake the appetite tends, is called the virtuous; for the virtuous 
is that which is desired for its own sake; but that which terminates the 
movement of the appetite in the form of rest in the thing desired, is 
called the pleasant.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Goodness, so far as it is identical with being, is divided 
by the ten predicaments. But this division belongs to it according to its 
proper formality.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: This division is not by opposite things; but by opposite 
aspects. Now those things are called pleasing which have no other 
formality under which they are desirable except the pleasant, being 
sometimes hurtful and contrary to virtue. Whereas the useful applies to 
such as have nothing desirable in themselves, but are desired only as 
helpful to something further, as the taking of bitter medicine; while the 
virtuous is predicated of such as are desirable in themselves. 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[5] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Goodness is not divided into these three as something 
univocal to be predicated equally of them all; but as something 
analogical to be predicated of them according to priority and 
posteriority. Hence it is predicated chiefly of the virtuous; then of the 
pleasant; and lastly of the useful.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] Out. Para. 1/1

THE GOODNESS OF GOD (FOUR ARTICLES)

 We next consider the goodness of God; under which head there are four 
points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether goodness belongs to God?

 (2) Whether God is the supreme good?

 (3) Whether He alone is essentially good?

 (4) Whether all things are good by the divine goodness?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is good?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that to be good does not belong to God. For goodness 
consists in mode, species and order. But these do not seem to belong to 
God; since God is immense and is not ordered to anything else. Therefore 
to be good does not belong to God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, the good is what all things desire. But all things do 
not desire God, because all things do not know Him; and nothing is 
desired unless it is known. Therefore to be good does not belong to God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written (Lam. 3:25): "The Lord is good to them 
that hope in Him, to the soul that seeketh Him."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, To be good belongs pre-eminently to God. For a thing is 
good according to its desirableness. Now everything seeks after its own 
perfection; and the perfection and form of an effect consist in a certain 
likeness to the agent, since every agent makes its like; and hence the 
agent itself is desirable and has the nature of good. For the very thing 
which is desirable in it is the participation of its likeness. Therefore, 
since God is the first effective cause of all things, it is manifest that 
the aspect of good and of desirableness belong to Him; and hence 
Dionysius (Div. Nom. iv) attributes good to God as to the first efficient 
cause, saying that, God is called good "as by Whom all things subsist."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: To have mode, species and order belongs to the essence of 
caused good; but good is in God as in its cause, and hence it belongs to 
Him to impose mode, species and order on others; wherefore these three 
things are in God as in their cause.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: All things, by desiring their own perfection, desire God 
Himself, inasmuch as the perfections of all things are so many 
similitudes of the divine being; as appears from what is said above (Q[4]
, A[3]). And so of those things which desire God, some know Him as He is 
Himself, and this is proper to the rational  creature; others know some 
participation of His goodness, and this belongs also to sensible 
knowledge; others have a natural desire without knowledge, as being 
directed to their ends by a higher intelligence.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is the supreme good?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is not the supreme good. For the supreme good 
adds something to good; otherwise it would belong to every good. But 
everything which is an addition to anything else is a compound thing: 
therefore the supreme good is a compound. But God is supremely simple; as 
was shown above (Q[3], A[7]). Therefore God is not the supreme good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, "Good is what all desire," as the Philosopher says 
(Ethic. i, 1). Now what all desire is nothing but God, Who is the end of 
all things: therefore there is no other good but God. This appears also 
from what is said (Lk. 18:19): "None is good but God alone." But we use 
the word supreme in comparison with others, as e.g. supreme heat is used 
in comparison with all other heats. Therefore God cannot be called the 
supreme good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, supreme implies comparison. But things not in the same 
genus are not comparable; as, sweetness is not properly greater or less 
than a line. Therefore, since God is not in the same genus as other good 
things, as appears above (Q[3], A[5]; Q[4], A[3]) it seems that God 
cannot be called the supreme good in relation to others.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. ii) that, the Trinity of the 
divine persons is "the supreme good, discerned by purified minds."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, God is the supreme good simply, and not only as existing 
in any genus or order of things. For good is attributed to God, as was 
said in the preceding article, inasmuch as all desired perfections flow 
from Him as from the first cause. They do not, however, flow from Him as 
from a univocal agent, as shown above (Q[4], A[2]); but as from an agent 
which does not agree with its effects either in species or genus. Now the 
likeness of an effect in the univocal cause is found uniformly; but in 
the equivocal cause it is found more excellently, as, heat is in the sun 
more excellently than it is in fire. Therefore as good is in God as in 
the first, but not the univocal, cause of all things, it must be in Him 
in a most excellent way; and therefore He is called the supreme good.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: The supreme good does not add to good any absolute thing, 
but only a relation. Now a relation of God to creatures, is not a reality 
in God, but in the creature; for it is in God in our idea only: as, what 
is knowable is so called with relation to knowledge, not that it depends 
on knowledge, but because knowledge depends on it. Thus it is not 
necessary that  there should be composition in the supreme good, but only 
that other things are deficient in comparison with it.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: When we say that good is what all desire, it is not to be 
understood that every kind of good thing is desired by all; but that 
whatever is desired has the nature of good. And when it is said, "None is 
good but God alone," this is to be understood of essential goodness, as 
will be explained in the next article.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Things not of the same genus are in no way comparable to 
each other if indeed they are in different genera. Now we say that God is 
not in the same genus with other good things; not that He is any other 
genus, but that He is outside genus, and is the principle of every genus; 
and thus He is compared to others by excess, and it is this kind of 
comparison the supreme good implies.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether to be essentially good belongs to God alone?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that to be essentially good does not belong to God 
alone. For as "one" is convertible with "being," so is "good"; as we said 
above (Q[5], A[1]). But every being is one essentially, as appears from 
the Philosopher (Metaph. iv); therefore every being is good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, if good is what all things desire, since being itself is 
desired by all, then the being of each thing is its good. But everything 
is a being essentially; therefore every being is good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, everything is good by its own goodness. Therefore if 
there is anything which is not good essentially, it is necessary to say 
that its goodness is not its own essence. Therefore its goodness, since 
it is a being, must be good; and if it is good by some other goodness, 
the same question applies to that goodness also; therefore we must either 
proceed to infinity, or come to some goodness which is not good by any 
other goodness. Therefore the first supposition holds good. Therefore 
everything is good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Boethius says (De Hebdom.), that "all things but God 
are good by participation." Therefore they are not good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, God alone is good essentially. For everything is called 
good according to its perfection. Now perfection of a thing is threefold: 
first, according to the constitution of its own being; secondly, in 
respect of any accidents being added as necessary for its perfect 
operation; thirdly, perfection consists in the attaining to something 
else as the end. Thus, for instance, the first perfection of fire 
consists in its existence, which it has through its own substantial form; 
its secondary perfection consists in heat, lightness and dryness, and the 
like; its third  perfection is to rest in its own place. This triple 
perfection belongs to no creature by its own essence; it belongs to God 
only, in Whom alone essence is existence; in Whom there are no accidents; 
since whatever belongs to others accidentally belongs to Him essentially; 
as, to be powerful, wise and the like, as appears from what is stated 
above (Q[3], A[6]); and He is not directed to anything else as to an end, 
but is Himself the last end of all things. Hence it is manifest that God 
alone has every kind of perfection by His own essence; therefore He 
Himself alone is good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: "One" does not include the idea of perfection, but only of 
indivision, which belongs to everything according to its own essence. Now 
the essences of simple things are undivided both actually and 
potentially, but the essences of compounds are undivided only actually; 
and therefore everything must be one essentially, but not good 
essentially, as was shown above.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Although everything is good in that it has being, yet the 
essence of a creature is not very being; and therefore it does not follow 
that a creature is good essentially.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The goodness of a creature is not its very essence, but 
something superadded; it is either its existence, or some added 
perfection, or the order to its end. Still, the goodness itself thus 
added is good, just as it is being. But for this reason is it called 
being because by it something has being, not because it itself has being 
through something else: hence for this reason is it called good because 
by it something is good, and not because it itself has some other 
goodness whereby it is good.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether all things are good by the divine goodness?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that all things are good by the divine goodness. For 
Augustine says (De Trin. viii), "This and that are good; take away this 
and that, and see good itself if thou canst; and so thou shalt see God, 
good not by any other good, but the good of every good." But everything 
is good by its own good; therefore everything is good by that very good 
which is God.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, as Boethius says (De Hebdom.), all things are called 
good, accordingly as they are directed to God, and this is by reason of 
the divine goodness; therefore all things are good by the divine goodness.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, All things are good, inasmuch as they have being. But 
they are not called beings through the divine being, but through their 
own being; therefore all things are not good by the divine goodness, but 
by their own goodness.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Body Para. 1/4

 I answer that, As regards relative things, we must admit extrinsic 
denomination; as, a thing is denominated "placed" from "place," and 
"measured" from "measure." But as regards absolute things opinions 
differ. Plato held the existence of separate ideas  (Q[84], A[4]) of all 
things, and that individuals were denominated by them as participating in 
the separate ideas; for instance, that Socrates is called man according 
to the separate idea of man. Now just as he laid down separate ideas of 
man and horse which he called absolute man and absolute horse, so 
likewise he laid down separate ideas of "being" and of "one," and these 
he called absolute being and absolute oneness; and by participation of 
these, everything was called "being" or "one"; and what was thus absolute 
being and absolute one, he said was the supreme good. And because good is 
convertible with being, as one is also; he called God the absolute good, 
from whom all things are called good by way of participation.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Body Para. 2/4

 Although this opinion appears to be unreasonable in affirming separate 
ideas of natural things as subsisting of themselves---as Aristotle argues 
in many ways---still, it is absolutely true that there is first something 
which is essentially being and essentially good, which we call God, as 
appears from what is shown above (Q[2], A[3]), and Aristotle agrees with 
this. Hence from the first being, essentially such, and good, everything 
can be called good and a being, inasmuch as it participates in it by way 
of a certain assimilation which is far removed and defective; as appears 
from the above (Q[4], A[3]).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Body Para. 3/4

 Everything is therefore called good from the divine goodness, as from 
the first exemplary effective and final principle of all goodness. 
Nevertheless, everything is called good by reason of the similitude of 
the divine goodness belonging to it, which is formally its own goodness, 
whereby it is denominated good. And so of all things there is one 
goodness, and yet many goodnesses.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[6] A[4] Body Para. 4/4

 This is a sufficient Reply to the Objections.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] Out. Para. 1/2

THE INFINITY OF GOD (FOUR ARTICLES)

 After considering the divine perfection we must consider the divine 
infinity, and God's existence in things: for God is everywhere, and in 
all things, inasmuch as He is boundless and infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] Out. Para. 2/2

 Concerning the first, there are four points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether God is infinite?

 (2) Whether anything besides Him is infinite in essence?

 (3) Whether anything can be infinitude in magnitude?

 (4) Whether an infinite multitude can exist?


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether God is infinite?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that God is not infinite. For everything infinite is 
imperfect, as the Philosopher says; because it has parts and matter, as 
is said in Phys. iii. But God is most perfect; therefore He is not 
infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1 

 OBJ 2: Further, according to the Philosopher (Phys. i), finite and 
infinite belong to quantity. But there is no quantity in God, for He is 
not a body, as was shown above (Q[3], A[1]). Therefore it does not belong 
to Him to be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, what is here in such a way as not to be elsewhere, is 
finite according to place. Therefore that which is a thing in such a way 
as not to be another thing, is finite according to substance. But God is 
this, and not another; for He is not a stone or wood. Therefore God is 
not infinite in substance.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, 4) that "God is 
infinite and eternal, and boundless."

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, All the ancient philosophers attribute infinitude to the 
first principle, as is said (Phys. iii), and with reason; for they 
considered that things flow forth infinitely from the first principle. 
But because some erred concerning the nature of the first principle, as a 
consequence they erred also concerning its infinity; forasmuch as they 
asserted that matter was the first principle; consequently they 
attributed to the first principle a material infinity to the effect that 
some infinite body was the first principle of things.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Body Para. 2/3

 We must consider therefore that a thing is called infinite because it is 
not finite. Now matter is in a way made finite by form, and the form by 
matter. Matter indeed is made finite by form, inasmuch as matter, before 
it receives its form, is in potentiality to many forms; but on receiving 
a form, it is terminated by that one. Again, form is made finite by 
matter, inasmuch as form, considered in itself, is common to many; but 
when received in matter, the form is determined to this one particular 
thing. Now matter is perfected by the form by which it is made finite; 
therefore infinite as attributed to matter, has the nature of something 
imperfect; for it is as it were formless matter. On the other hand, form 
is not made perfect by matter, but rather is contracted by matter; and 
hence the infinite, regarded on the part of the form not determined by 
matter, has the nature of something perfect. Now being is the most formal 
of all things, as appears from what is shown above (Q[4], A[1], OBJ[3]). 
Since therefore the divine being is not a being received in anything, but 
He is His own subsistent being as was shown above (Q[3], A[4]), it is 
clear that God Himself is infinite and perfect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] Body Para. 3/3

 From this appears the Reply to the First Objection.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Quantity is terminated by its form, which can be seen in 
the fact that a figure which consists in quantity terminated, is a kind 
of quantitative form. Hence the infinite of quantity is the infinite of 
matter; such a kind of infinite cannot be attributed to God; as was said 
above, in this article.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The fact that the being of God is self-subsisting, not 
received in any other, and is thus called  infinite, shows Him to be 
distinguished from all other beings, and all others to be apart from Him. 
Even so, were there such a thing as a self-subsisting whiteness, the very 
fact that it did not exist in anything else, would make it distinct from 
every other whiteness existing in a subject.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether anything but God can be essentially infinite?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that something else besides God can be essentially 
infinite. For the power of anything is proportioned to its essence. Now 
if the essence of God is infinite, His power must also be infinite. 
Therefore He can produce an infinite effect, since the extent of a power 
is known by its effect.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, whatever has infinite power, has an infinite essence. 
Now the created intellect has an infinite power; for it apprehends the 
universal, which can extend itself to an infinitude of singular things. 
Therefore every created intellectual substance is infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, primary matter is something other than God, as was shown 
above (Q[3], A[8]). But primary matter is infinite. Therefore something 
besides God can be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, The infinite cannot have a beginning, as said in Phys. 
iii. But everything outside God is from God as from its first principle. 
Therefore besides God nothing can be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] Body Para. 1/1

 I answer that, Things other than God can be relatively infinite, but not 
absolutely infinite. For with regard to infinite as applied to matter, it 
is manifest that everything actually existing possesses a form; and thus 
its matter is determined by form. But because matter, considered as 
existing under some substantial form, remains in potentiality to many 
accidental forms, which is absolutely finite can be relatively infinite; 
as, for example, wood is finite according to its own form, but still it 
is relatively infinite, inasmuch as it is in potentiality to an infinite 
number of shapes. But if we speak of the infinite in reference to form, 
it is manifest that those things, the forms of which are in matter, are 
absolutely finite, and in no way infinite. If, however, any created forms 
are not received into matter, but are self-subsisting, as some think is 
the case with angels, these will be relatively infinite, inasmuch as such 
kinds of forms are not terminated, nor contracted by any matter. But 
because a created form thus subsisting has being, and yet is not its own 
being, it follows that its being is received and contracted to a 
determinate nature. Hence it cannot be absolutely infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: It is against the nature of a made thing for its essence to 
be its existence; because subsisting being is not a created being; hence 
it is against the nature of a made thing to be absolutely infinite. 
Therefore, as God, although He has infinite power, cannot make a thing to 
be not made (for this would imply that two contradictories are true at 
the same time), so likewise He  cannot make anything to be absolutely 
infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: The fact that the power of the intellect extends itself in 
a way to infinite things, is because the intellect is a form not in 
matter, but either wholly separated from matter, as is the angelic 
substance, or at least an intellectual power, which is not the act of any 
organ, in the intellectual soul joined to a body.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Primary matter does not exist by itself in nature, since it 
is not actually being, but potentially only; hence it is something 
concreated rather than created. Nevertheless, primary matter even as a 
potentiality is not absolutely infinite, but relatively, because its 
potentiality extends only to natural forms.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether an actually infinite magnitude can exist?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that there can be something actually infinite in 
magnitude. For in mathematics there is no error, since "there is no lie 
in things abstract," as the Philosopher says (Phys. ii). But mathematics 
uses the infinite in magnitude; thus, the geometrician in his 
demonstrations says, "Let this line be infinite." Therefore it is not 
impossible for a thing to be infinite in magnitude.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, what is not against the nature of anything, can agree 
with it. Now to be infinite is not against the nature of magnitude; but 
rather both the finite and the infinite seem to be properties of 
quantity. Therefore it is not impossible for some magnitude to be 
infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, magnitude is infinitely divisible, for the continuous is 
defined that which is infinitely divisible, as is clear from Phys. iii. 
But contraries are concerned about one and the same thing. Since 
therefore addition is opposed to division, and increase opposed to 
diminution, it appears that magnitude can be increased to infinity. 
Therefore it is possible for magnitude to be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 4: Further, movement and time have quantity and continuity derived 
from the magnitude over which movement passes, as is said in Phys. iv. 
But it is not against the nature of time and movement to be infinite, 
since every determinate indivisible in time and circular movement is both 
a beginning and an end. Therefore neither is it against the nature of 
magnitude to be infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, Every body has a surface. But every body which has a 
surface is finite; because surface is the term of a finite body. 
Therefore all bodies are finite. The same applies both to surface and to 
a line. Therefore nothing is infinite in magnitude.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Body Para. 1/4

 I answer that, It is one thing to be infinite in essence, and  another 
to be infinite in magnitude. For granted that a body exists infinite in 
magnitude, as fire or air, yet this could not be infinite in essence, 
because its essence would be terminated in a species by its form, and 
confined to individuality by matter. And so assuming from these premises 
that no creature is infinite in essence, it still remains to inquire 
whether any creature can be infinite in magnitude.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Body Para. 2/4

 We must therefore observe that a body, which is a complete magnitude, 
can be considered in two ways; mathematically, in respect to its quantity 
only; and naturally, as regards its matter and form.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Body Para. 3/4

 Now it is manifest that a natural body cannot be actually infinite. For 
every natural body has some determined substantial form. Since therefore 
the accidents follow upon the substantial form, it is necessary that 
determinate accidents should follow upon a determinate form; and among 
these accidents is quantity. So every natural body has a greater or 
smaller determinate quantity. Hence it is impossible for a natural body 
to be infinite. The same appears from movement; because every natural 
body has some natural movement; whereas an infinite body could not have 
any natural movement; neither direct, because nothing moves naturally by 
a direct movement unless it is out of its place; and this could not 
happen to an infinite body, for it would occupy every place, and thus 
every place would be indifferently its own place. Neither could it move 
circularly; forasmuch as circular motion requires that one part of the 
body is necessarily transferred to a place occupied by another part, and 
this could not happen as regards an infinite circular body: for if two 
lines be drawn from the centre, the farther they extend from the centre, 
the farther they are from each other; therefore, if a body were infinite, 
the lines would be infinitely distant from each other; and thus one could 
never occupy the place belonging to any other.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] Body Para. 4/4

 The same applies to a mathematical body. For if we imagine a 
mathematical body actually existing, we must imagine it under some form, 
because nothing is actual except by its form; hence, since the form of 
quantity as such is figure, such a body must have some figure, and so 
would be finite; for figure is confined by a term or boundary.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: A geometrician does not need to assume a line actually 
infinite, but takes some actually finite line, from which he subtracts 
whatever he finds necessary; which line he calls infinite.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Although the infinite is not against the nature of 
magnitude in general, still it is against the nature of any species of 
it; thus, for instance, it is against the nature of a bicubical or 
tricubical magnitude, whether circular or triangular, and so on. Now what 
is not possible in any species cannot exist in the genus; hence there 
cannot be any infinite magnitude, since no species of magnitude is 
infinite. 

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: The infinite in quantity, as was shown above, belongs to 
matter. Now by division of the whole we approach to matter, forasmuch as 
parts have the aspect of matter; but by addition we approach to the whole 
which has the aspect of a form. Therefore the infinite is not in the 
addition of magnitude, but only in division.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 4: Movement and time are whole, not actually but successively; 
hence they have potentiality mixed with actuality. But magnitude is an 
actual whole; therefore the infinite in quantity refers to matter, and 
does not agree with the totality of magnitude; yet it agrees with the 
totality of time and movement: for it is proper to matter to be in 
potentiality.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1

Whether an infinite multitude can exist?

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 1: It seems that an actually infinite multitude is possible. For it 
is not impossible for a potentiality to be made actual. But number can be 
multiplied to infinity. Therefore it is possible for an infinite 
multitude actually to exist.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 2: Further, it is possible for any individual of any species to be 
made actual. But the species of figures are infinite. Therefore an 
infinite number of actual figures is possible.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1

 OBJ 3: Further, things not opposed to each other do not obstruct each 
other. But supposing a multitude of things to exist, there can still be 
many others not opposed to them. Therefore it is not impossible for 
others also to coexist with them, and so on to infinitude; therefore an 
actual infinite number of things is possible.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1

 On the contrary, It is written, "Thou hast ordered all things in 
measure, and number, and weight" (Wis. 11:21).

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Body Para. 1/3

 I answer that, A twofold opinion exists on this subject. Some, as 
Avicenna and Algazel, said that it was impossible for an actually 
infinite multitude to exist absolutely; but that an accidentally infinite 
multitude was not impossible. A multitude is said to be infinite 
absolutely, when an infinite multitude is necessary that something may 
exist. Now this is impossible; because it would entail something 
dependent on an infinity for its existence; and hence its generation 
could never come to be, because it is impossible to pass through an 
infinite medium.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Body Para. 2/3

 A multitude is said to be accidentally infinite when its existence as 
such is not necessary, but accidental. This can be shown, for example, in 
the work of a carpenter requiring a certain absolute multitude; namely, 
art in the soul, the movement of the hand, and a hammer; and supposing 
that such things were infinitely multiplied, the carpentering work would 
never be finished, forasmuch as it would depend on an infinite number of 
causes. But  the multitude of hammers, inasmuch as one may be broken and 
another used, is an accidental multitude; for it happens by accident that 
many hammers are used, and it matters little whether one or two, or many 
are used, or an infinite number, if the work is carried on for an 
infinite time. In this way they said that there can be an accidentally 
infinite multitude.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] Body Para. 3/3

 This, however, is impossible; since every kind of multitude must belong 
to a species of multitude. Now the species of multitude are to be 
reckoned by the species of numbers. But no species of number is infinite; 
for every number is multitude measured by one. Hence it is impossible for 
there to be an actually infinite multitude, either absolute or 
accidental. Likewise multitude in nature is created; and everything 
created is comprehended under some clear intention of the Creator; for no 
agent acts aimlessly. Hence everything created must be comprehended in a 
certain number. Therefore it is impossible for an actually infinite 
multitude to exist, even accidentally. But a potentially infinite 
multitude is possible; because the increase of multitude follows upon the 
division of magnitude; since the more a thing is divided, the greater 
number of things result. Hence, as the infinite is to be found 
potentially in the division of the continuous, because we thus approach 
matter, as was shown in the preceding article, by the same rule, the 
infinite can be also found potentially in the addition of multitude.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 1: Every potentiality is made actual according to its mode of 
being; for instance, a day is reduced to act successively, and not all at 
once. Likewise the infinite in multitude is reduced to act successively, 
and not all at once; because every multitude can be succeeded by another 
multitude to infinity.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 2: Species of figures are infinite by infinitude of number. 
Now there are various species of figures, such as trilateral, 
quadrilateral and so on; and as an infinitely numerable multitude is not 
all at once reduced to act, so neither is the multitude of figures.

Aquin.: SMT FP Q[7] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1

 Reply OBJ 3: Although the supposition of some things does not preclude 
the supposition of others, still the supposition of an infinite number is 
opposed to any single species of multitude. Hence it is not possible for 
an actually infinite multitude to exist.


Aquin.: SMT FP Q[8] Out. Para. 1/1

THE EXISTENCE OF GOD IN THINGS (FOUR ARTICLES)

 Since it evidently belongs to the infinite to be present everywhere, and 
in all things, we now consider whether this belongs to God; and 
concerning this there arise four points of inquiry:

 (1) Whether God is in all things?

 (2) Whether God is everywhere?

 (3) Whether God is everywhere by essence, power, and presence?

 (4) Whether to be everywhere belongs to God alone?