Inconvenient Lives

Robert H. Bork

Judging from the evidence, Americans do not view human life as 
sacrosanct. We engage in a variety of activities, from driving 
automobiles to constructing buildings, that we know will cause 
deaths. But the deliberate taking of the life of an individual has 
never been regarded as a matter of moral indifference. We debate 
the death penalty, for example, endlessly. It seems an anomaly, 
therefore, that we have so easily accepted practices that are the 
deliberate taking of identifiable individual lives. We have turned 
abortion into a constitutional right; one state has made assisted 
suicide a statutory right and two federal circuit courts, not to 
be outdone, have made it a constitutional right; campaigns to 
legalize euthanasia are underway. It is entirely predictable that 
many of the elderly, ill, and infirm will be killed, and often 
without their consent. This is where radical individualism has 
taken us.

When a society revises its attitude toward life and death, we can 
see the direction of its moral movement. The revision of American 
thought and practice about life questions began with abortion, and 
examination of the moral confusion attending that issue helps us 
understand more general developments in public morality.

The necessity for reflection about abortion does not depend on, 
but is certainly made dramatic by, the fact that there are 
approximately a million and a half abortions annually in the 
United States. To put it another way, since the Supreme Court's 
1973 decision in <Roe v. Wade>, there have been perhaps over 
thirty million abortions in the United States. Three out of ten 
conceptions today end in the destruction of the fetus. These 
facts, standing alone, do not decide the issue of morality, but 
they do mean that the issue is hugely significant.

The issue is also heated, polarizing, and often debated on both 
sides in angry, moralistic terms. I will refrain from such 
rhetoric because for most of my life I held a position on the 
subject very different from the one I now take. For years I 
adopted, without bothering to think, the attitude common among 
secular, affluent, university-educated people who took the 
propriety of abortion for granted, even when it was illegal. The 
practice's illegality, like that of drinking alcohol during 
Prohibition, was thought to reflect merely unenlightened prejudice 
or religious conviction, the two being regarded as much the same. 
From time to time, someone would say that it was a difficult moral 
problem, but there was rarely any doubt how the problem should be 
resolved. I remember a woman at Yale saying, without any 
disagreement from those around her, that "The fetus isn't nothing, 
but I am for the mother's right to abort it." I probably nodded. 
Most of us had a vague and unexamined notion that while the fetus 
wasn't nothing, it was also not fully human.1 The slightest 
reflection would have suggested that non-human or semi-human blobs 
of tissue do not magically turn into human beings.

Qualms about abortion began to arise when I first read about fetal 
pain. There is no doubt that, after its nervous system has 
developed to a degree, the fetus being dismembered or poisoned in 
the womb feels excruciating pain. For that reason, many people 
would confine abortion to the early stages of pregnancy but have 
no objection to it then. There are, on the other hand, people who 
oppose abortion at any stage and those who regard it as a right at 
any stage up to the moment of birth. But in thinking about 
abortion-especially abortion at any stage-it is necessary to 
address two questions. Is abortion always the killing of a human 
being? If it is, is that killing done simply for convenience? I 
think there can be no doubt that the answer to the first question 
is, yes; and the answer to the second is, almost always.2

The question of whether abortion is the termination of a human 
life is a relatively simple one. It has been described as a 
question requiring no more than a knowledge of high school 
biology. There may be doubt that high school biology courses are 
clear on the subject these days, but consider what we know. The 
male sperm and the female egg each contains twenty-three 
chromosomes. Upon fertilization, a single cell results containing 
forty-six chromosomes, which is what all humans have, including, 
of course, the mother and the father. But the new organism's 
forty-six chromosomes are in a different combination from those of 
either parent; the new organism is unique. It is not an organ of 
the mother's body but a different individual. This cell produces 
specifically human proteins and enzymes from the beginning. Its 
chromosomes will heavily influence its destiny until the day of 
its death, whether that death is at the age of ninety or one month 
after conception.

The cell will multiply and develop, in accordance with its 
individual chromosomes, and, when it enters the world, will be 
recognizably a human baby. From single-cell fertilized egg to baby 
to teenager to adult to old age to death is a single process of 
one individual, not a series of different individuals replacing 
each other. It is impossible to draw a line anywhere after the 
moment of fertilization and say before this point the creature is 
not human but after this point it is. It has all the attributes of 
a human from the beginning, and those attributes were in the 
forty-six chromosomes with which it began. Francis Crick, the 
Nobel laureate and biophysicist, is quoted as having estimated 
that "the amount of information contained in the chromosomes of a 
single fertilized human egg is equivalent to about a thousand 
printed volumes of books, each as large as a volume of the 
Encyclopedia Britannica." Such a creature is not a blob of tissue 
or, as the Roe opinion so felicitously put it, a "potential life." 
As someone has said, it is a life with potential.

It is impossible to say that the killing of the organism at any 
moment after it originated is not the killing of a human being. 
Yet there are those who say just that by redefining what a human 
being is. Redefining what it means to be a human being will prove 
dangerous in contexts other than abortion. One of the more 
primitive arguments put forward is that in the embryonic stage, 
which lasts about two months after conception, the creature does 
not look human. One man said to me, "Have you ever seen an embryo? 
It looks like a guppy." A writer whose work I greatly respect 
refers to "the patently inhuman fetus of four weeks." A cartoonist 
made fun of a well-known anti-abortion doctor by showing him 
pointing to the microscopic dot that is the zygote and saying, 
"We'll call him Timmy." It is difficult to know what the 
appearance of Timmy has to do with the humanity of the fetus. I 
suspect appearance is made an issue because the more recognizably 
a baby the fetus becomes, the more our emotions reject the idea of 
destroying it. But those are uninstructed emotions, not emotions 
based on a recognition of what the fetus is from the beginning.

Other common arguments are that the embryo or fetus is not fully 
sentient, or that it cannot live outside the mother's womb, or 
that the fetus is not fully a person unless it is valued by its 
mother. These seem utterly insubstantial arguments. A newborn is 
not fully sentient, nor is a person in an advanced stage of 
Alzheimer's disease. There are people who would allow the killing 
of the newborn and the senile, but I doubt that is a view with 
general acceptance. At least not yet. Equally irrelevant to the 
discussion is the fact that the fetus cannot survive outside the 
womb. Neither can a baby survive without the nurture of others, 
usually the parents. Why dependency, which lasts for years after 
birth, should justify terminating life is inexplicable. No more 
apparent is the logic of the statement that a fetus is a person 
only if the mother values its life. That is a tautology: an 
abortion is justified if the mother wants an abortion.

In discussing abortion, James Q. Wilson wrote, "The moral debate 
over abortion centers on the point in the development of the 
fertilized ovum when it has acquired those characteristics that 
entitle it to moral respect." He did not, apparently, think the 
cell resulting from conception was so entitled. Wilson gave an 
example of moral respect persisting in difficult circumstances: 
"An elderly man who has been a devoted husband and father but who 
now lies comatose in a vegetative state barely seems to be alive, 
. . . yet we experience great moral anguish in deciding whether to 
withdraw his life support." In response, my wife was moved to 
observe, "But suppose the doctor told us that in eight months the 
man would recover, be fully human, and live a normal life as a 
unique individual. Is it even conceivable that we would remove his 
life-support system on the ground that his existence, like that of 
the fetus, is highly inconvenient to us and that he does not look 
human at the moment? There would be no moral anguish but instead a 
certainty that such an act would be a grave moral wrong."

It is certainly more likely that we would refuse to countenance an 
abortion if a sonogram showed a recognizable human being than if 
only a tiny, guppy- like being appeared. But that is an 
instinctive reaction and instinctive reactions are not always the 
best guide to moral choice. Intellect must play a role as well. 
What if biology convinces us that the guppy-like creature or the 
microscopic fertilized egg has exactly the same future, the same 
capacity to live a full human life, as does the fetus at three 
months or at seven months or the infant at birth? "It is difficult 
to see," my wife added, "that the decision in the imagined case of 
the comatose elderly man who in time will recover is different 
from the abortion decision." In both cases, it is only a matter of 
time. The difference is that the death of the elderly man would 
deprive him of a few years of life while the aborted embryo or 
fetus loses an entire lifetime.

The issue is not, I think, one of appearance, sentience, or 
anything other than prospective life that is denied the individual 
by abortion. In introductory ethics courses, there used to be a 
question put: If you could obtain a hundred million dollars by 
pressing a button that would kill an elderly Chinese mandarin whom 
you had never seen, and if nobody would know what you had done, 
would you press the button? That seems to me the same issue as the 
abortion decision, except that the unborn child has a great deal 
longer to live if you don't press that particular button. Most of 
us, I suspect, would like to think we would not kill the mandarin. 
The characteristics of appearance, sentience, ability to live 
without assistance, and being valued by others cannot be the 
characteristics that entitle you to sufficient moral respect to be 
allowed to go on living. What characteristic does, then? It must 
lie in the fact that you are alive with the prospect of years of 
life ahead. That characteristic the unborn child has.

That seems to me an adequate ground to reject the argument made by 
Peter Singer last year in the London <Spectator> that supports not 
only abortion but infanticide. He writes that it is doubtful that 
a fetus becomes conscious until well after the time most abortions 
are performed and even if it is conscious, that would not put the 
fetus at a level of awareness comparable to that of "a dog, let 
alone a chimpanzee. If on the other hand it is self-awareness, 
rather than mere consciousness, that grounds a right to life, that 
does not arise in a human being until some time after birth."

Aware that this line leaves out of account the potential of the 
child for a full human life, Singer responds that "in a world that 
is already over-populated, and in which the regulation of 
fertility is universally accepted, the argument that we should 
bring all potential people into existence is not persuasive." That 
is disingenuous. If overpopulation were a fact, that would hardly 
justify killing humans. If overpopulation were taken to be a 
justification, it would allow the killing of any helpless 
population, preferably without the infliction of pain.

Most contraceptive methods of regulating fertility do not raise 
the same moral issue as abortion because they do not permit the 
joining of the sperm and the egg. Until the sperm and the egg 
unite, there is no human being. Singer goes on to make the 
unsubstantiated claim that "just as the human being develops 
gradually in a physical sense, so too does its moral significance 
gradually increase." That contention is closely allied to the 
physical appearance argument and is subject to the same rebuttal. 
One wonders at measuring moral significance by physique. If a 
person gradually degenerated physically, would his moral 
significance gradually decline?

Many who favor the abortion right understand that humans are being 
killed. Certainly the doctors who perform and nurses who assist at 
abortions know that. So do nonprofessionals. Otherwise, abortion 
would not be smothered in euphemisms. Thus, we hear the language 
of "choice," "reproductive rights," and "medical procedures." 
Those are oddly inadequate terms to describe the right to end the 
life of a human being. It has been remarked that "pro-choice" is 
an odd term since the individual whose life is at stake has no 
choice in the matter. These are ways of talking around the point 
that hide the truth from others and, perhaps, from one's self. 
President Clinton speaks of keeping abortion "safe, legal, and 
rare." Why rare, if it is merely a choice, a medical procedure 
without moral problems?

That there are severe moral problems is becoming clear even to 
many who favor abortion. That is probably why, as Candace C. 
Crandall observed last year in the <Women's Quarterly>, "the 
morale of the prochoice side of the abortion stalemate has visibly 
collapsed." The reason: "Proponents of abortion rights overcame 
Americans' qualms about the procedure with a long series of claims 
about the benefits of unrestricted abortion on demand. Without 
exception, those claims have proved false." The proponents claimed 
that <Roe v. Wade> rescued women from death during unsafe, back-
alley abortions, but it was the availability of antibiotics 
beginning in the 1940s and improved medical techniques that made 
abortion safe well before <Roe.> It was argued that abortion on 
demand would guarantee that every child was a wanted child, would 
keep children from being born into poverty, reduce illegitimacy 
rates, and help end child abuse. Child poverty rates, illegitimacy 
rates, and child abuse have all soared. We heard that abortion 
should be a decision between a woman and her doctor. The idea of a 
woman and her personal physician deliberating about the choice is 
a fantasy: women are going to specialized abortion clinics that 
offer little support or counseling. (Crandall does not address the 
point, but it is difficult to see that bringing a doctor in for 
consultation would change the nature of the decision about taking 
human life.) She does note, however, that many women use abortion 
for birth control.

Crandall says she sympathizes with abortion-rights advocates. But 
on her own showing, it is difficult to see why. No anti-abortion 
advocate could make it clearer that human lives are being 
destroyed at the rate of 1.5 million a year for convenience.

The author Naomi Wolf, who favors the right to abort, has 
challenged the feminists whose rhetoric seeks to disguise the 
truth that a human being is killed by abortion. In a 1995 article 
in the <New Republic>, she asks for "an abortion-rights movement 
willing publicly to mourn the evil-necessary evil though it may 
be-that is abortion." But she asks a question and gives an answer 
about her support for abortion rights that is troublesome: "But 
how, one might ask, can I square a recognition of the humanity of 
the fetus, and the moral gravity of destroying it, with a pro-
choice position? The answer can only be found in the context of a 
paradigm abandoned by the left and misused by the right: the 
paradigm of sin and redemption."

That seems an odd paradigm for this problem. It is one thing to 
have sinned, atoned, and sought redemption. It seems quite another 
to justify planning to sin on the ground that you also plan to 
seek redemption afterward. That justification seems even stranger 
for repeat abortions, which Wolf says are at least 43 percent of 
the total. Sin plus redemption falls short as a resolution of her 
dilemma. If that were an adequate resolution, it would seem to 
follow, given the humanity of the fetus, that infanticide, the 
killing of the elderly, indeed any killing for convenience, would 
be licensed if atonement and redemption were planned in advance.

Nor is it clear why the evil is necessary. It is undeniable that 
bearing and rearing a child sometimes places a great burden on a 
woman or a family. That fact does not, however, answer the 
question whether the burden justifies destroying a human life. In 
most other contexts, we would say such a burden is not sufficient 
justification. The fact is, in any event, that the burden need not 
be borne. Putting the child up for adoption is an alternative. The 
only drawback is that others will know the woman is pregnant. If 
that is the reason to choose abortion, then the killing really is 
for convenience.

But it is clear, in any event, that the vast majority of  all 
abortions are for convenience. In those cases,  abortion is used 
as merely one more technique of  birth control. A 1987 survey of 
the reasons given by  women for having abortions made by 
researchers  with the Alan Guttmacher Institute, which is very  
much pro-abortion, demonstrated this fact. The following table 
shows the percentage of women who  gave the listed reasons.

Reason                                 Total Percentage

Woman is concerned about                       76
how having a baby could change
her life

Woman can't afford baby now                    68

Woman has problems with                        51
relationship or wants to avoid
single parenthood

Woman is unready for responsibility            31

Woman doesn't want others to know              31
she has had sex or is pregnant

Woman is not mature enough or is               30
too young to have a child

Woman has all the children she                 26
wanted, or has all grown-up children 

Husband or partner wants woman                 23
to have abortion

Fetus has possible health problem              13

Woman has health problem                        7

Woman's parents want her to                     7
have abortion

Woman was victim of rape or incest              1

Other                                           6


It is clear that the overwhelming number of abortions were for 
birth control unrelated to the health of the fetus or the woman. 
Moreover, of those who were concerned about a possible health 
problem of the fetus, only 8 percent said that a physician had 
told them that the fetus had a defect or was abnormal. The rest 
were worried because they had taken medication, drugs, or alcohol 
before realizing they were pregnant, but did not apparently obtain 
a medical confirmation of any problem. Of those aborting because 
of their own health, 53 percent said a doctor had told them their 
condition would be made worse by being pregnant. Some of the rest 
cited physical problems, and 11 percent gave a mental or emotional 
problem as the reason. Only 1 percent cited rape or incest.

The survey noted that "some 77 percent of women with incomes under 
100 percent or between 100 and 149 percent of the poverty level 
said they were having an abortion because they could not afford to 
have a child, compared with 69 percent of those with incomes 
between 150 and 199 percent and 60 percent of those with incomes 
at or above 200 percent of the poverty level." The can't-afford 
category thus included a great many women who, by most reckonings, 
could afford to have a baby and certainly could have put the baby 
up for adoption.

This demonstration that abortion is almost always a birth control 
technique rather than a response to a serious problem with the 
mother's or the fetus' health must have been a considerable 
embarrassment to the pro-abortion forces. Perhaps for that reason 
no survey by them seems to have been reported since. More recent 
statistics by anti-abortion groups, however, bear out the 
conclusions to be drawn from the Guttmacher Institute study. The 
reasons most women give for having an abortion are "social": a 
baby would affect their educations, jobs, lives, or they felt 
unable to handle it economically, their partners did not want 
babies, etc.

Perhaps the most instructive episode demonstrating the 
brutalization of our culture by abortion was the fight over 
"partial-birth abortions." These abortions are usually performed 
late in the pregnancy. The baby is delivered feet first until only 
the head remains within the mother. The aborting physician inserts 
scissors into the back of the infant's skull and opens the blades 
to produce a hole. The child's brains are then vacuumed out, the 
skull collapses, and the rest of the newly made corpse is removed. 
If the head had been allowed to come out of the mother, killing 
the baby then would be the criminal act of infanticide.

When it was proposed to outlaw this hideous procedure, which 
obviously causes extreme pain to the baby, the pro-abortion forces 
in Congress and elsewhere made false statements to fend off the 
legislation or to justify an anticipated presidential veto. 
Planned Parenthood and the National Abortion and Reproductive 
Rights Action League stated that the general anesthesia given the 
mother killed the fetus so that there is no such thing as a 
partial-birth abortion. Physicians promptly rebutted the claim. 
Local anesthesia, which is most often used in these abortions, has 
no effect on the baby and general anesthesia not only does not 
kill the baby, it provides little or no painkilling effect to the 
baby. The vice president of the Society for Obstetric Anesthesia 
and Perinatology said the claim was "crazy," noting that 
"anesthesia does not kill an infant if you don't kill the mother." 
Two doctors who perform partial-birth abortions stated that the 
majority of fetuses aborted in this fashion are alive until the 
end of the procedure.

Other opponents of a ban on partial-birth abortions claimed that 
it was used only when necessary to protect the mother's life. 
Unfortunately for that argument, the physician who is the best-
known practitioner of these abortions stated in 1993 that 80 
percent of them are "purely elective," not necessary to save the 
mother's life or health. Partial-birth understates the matter. The 
baby is outside the mother except for its head, which is kept in 
the mother only to avoid a charge of infanticide. Full birth is 
inches away and could easily be accomplished.

No amount of discussion, no citation of evidence, can alter the 
opinions of radical feminists about abortion. One evening I 
naively remarked in a talk that those who favor the right to abort 
would likely change their minds if they could be convinced that a 
human being was being killed. I was startled at the anger that 
statement provoked in several women present. One of them informed 
me in no uncertain terms that the issue had nothing to do with the 
humanity of the fetus but was entirely about the woman's freedom. 
It is here that radical egalitarianism reinforces radical 
individualism in supporting the abortion right. Justice Harry 
Blackmun, who wrote <Roe> and who never offered the slightest 
constitutional defense of it, simply remarked that the decision 
was a landmark on women's march to equality. Equality, in this 
view, means that if men do not bear children, women should not 
have to either. Abortion is seen as women's escape from the idea 
that biology is destiny, to escape from the tyranny of the family 
role.

Discussions about life and death in one area influence such 
decisions in others. Despite assurances that the abortion decision 
did not start us down a slippery and very steep slope, that is 
clearly where we are, and gathering speed. The systematic killing 
of unborn children in huge numbers is part of a general disregard 
for human life that has been growing for some time. Abortion by 
itself did not cause that disregard, but it certainly deepens and 
legitimates the nihilism that is spreading in our culture and 
finds killing for convenience acceptable. We are crossing lines, 
at first slowly and now with rapidity: killing unborn children for 
convenience; removing tissue from live fetuses; contemplating 
creating embryos for destruction in research; considering taking 
organs from living anencephalic babies; experimenting with 
assisted suicide; and contemplating euthanasia. Abortion has 
coarsened us. If it is permissible to kill the unborn human for 
convenience, it is surely permissible to kill those thought to be 
soon to die for the same reason. And it is inevitable that many 
who are not in danger of imminent death will be killed to relieve 
their families of burdens. Convenience is becoming the theme of 
our culture. Humans tend to be inconvenient at both ends of their 
lives.

ROBERT H. BORK is the John M. Olin Scholar in Legal Studies at the 
American Enterprise Institute. This article is adapted from his 
new book, <Slouching Towards Gomorrah>, published by ReganBooks, 
an imprint of HarperCollins. Copyright (c) 1996 by Robert H. Bork.

ENDNOTES

1 I objected to <Roe v. Wade> the moment it was decided not because of any doubts about abortion, but because the decision was a radical deformation of the Constitution. The Constitution has nothing to say about abortion, leaving it, like most subjects, to the judgment and moral sense of the American people and their elected representatives. <Roe> and the decisions reaffirming it are equal in their audacity and abuse of judicial office to <Dred Scott v. Sandford.> Just as <Dred Scott> forced a southern proslavery position on the nation, <Roe> is nothing more than the Supreme Court's imposition of the morality of our cultural elites.

2 In discussing abortion I will not address instances where most people, however they might ultimately decide the issue, would feel genuine moral anguish, cases, for example, where it is known that the child will be born with severe deformities. My purpose is not to solve all moral issues but simply to address the major ones. Abortions in cases of deformity, etc., are a very small fraction of the total and, because they introduce special factors, do not cast light on the direction of our culture as do abortions of healthy pre-borns performed for convenience.

This article appeared in the October 1996 issue of "First Things." 
To subscribe write First Things, Dept. FT, P.O. Box 3000, 
Denville, NJ 07834-9847, 1-800-783-4903. Published monthly except 
bimonthly June/July and August/September for $29.00 per year.

-------------------------------------------------------

   Provided courtesy of:

        Eternal Word Television Network
        PO Box 3610
        Manassas, VA 22110
        Voice: 703-791-2576
        Fax: 703-791-4250
        Web: http://www.ewtn.com
        Email address: sysop@ewtn.com

-------------------------------------------------------