"<Quid est Veritas?>" Human Freedom After Casey John R. Meyer A recent issue of <Crisis> contains an interesting article by Russell Hittinger entitled "Et tu, Justice Kennedy?",1 which provides a detailed historical review of the juridical <iter> and thought processes leading up and subsequent to <Roe v. Wade>. The principal thesis of that work is that the interpretation of <Roe> is centered upon a reaffirmation of what is commonly termed the "central holding" of <Roe>. The content of the "holding" notion includes two primary arguments: i) the Fourteenth Amendment understanding of "liberty" includes a woman's decision to abort a pre-viable fetus, and ii) overturning Roe poses a threat to "social stability," "the rule of law," and the "integrity of the judiciary." Hittinger comments that "what makes Casey different from our previous judge-made laws on abortion is the <migration> of the abortion right from privacy to liberty." The three cited justices explain that "at the heart of liberty is the right to <define> one's own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of life." Hittinger succinctly records for us the juridical itinerary culminating in the Casey decision, which for all practical purposes is a radical endorsement of the human person as self- constitutory. The <First Things> editorial of October summarizes the Court's view of human freedom as "the liberty of self-will, self-expression, and indeed self-constitution." Initially, the Supreme Court determined that "the right to privacy" prevents civil interference in the marital life of people. Thus state statutes forbidding the sale or use of contraceptives was declared unconstitutional (<Griswold v. Connecticut> [1965]) because it would allow an unjust invasion of the mutual marital relationship. In 1971 the Court ruled that the sale of drugs or instruments of a contraceptive nature cannot be prevented by State law (<Eisenstadt v. Baird>). The application of the "right to privacy" proved inadequate in this case because civil intervention affected only individuals and not the marital relationship <per se>. The earlier <Griswold> decision had described the "right to privacy" as "surrounding the marriage relationship" whereas in <Eisenstadt> it now comes to <inhere> in the individual. <Roe v. Wade> (1973) amplified the notion of this right to encompass a panoply of supposed individual values, psychological, social, economic, and others. All of these are very important but at the same time circumstantial considerations which do not alter the essential nature of the act of abortion. <Roe> effectively extracted the notion of the mutual relationship of the persons in the institution of matrimony by affirming the exclusive and unilateral right of one type of individual, the woman, to procure an abortion. In <Bowers V. Hardwick> (1986) the "right to privacy" was restricted to the marital state as the Court refused to <extend> the "right to privacy" to include homosexual sodomy. But in his dissenting opinion Justice Blackmun said that the notion of "right to privacy" had to be <redefined> by introducing the concept of "self-definition." He wrote that this right was essentially one of autonomy understood as "the ability to lay claim to one's own personality through free choice." The <Casey> decision actually makes use of this re-definition of "the right to privacy" in order to promote an almost unlimited conception of human freedom in the area of sexual activity, whether procreative or not. Whether there has been a "migration" of thought is less important than what this decision patently affirms: "human beings define who they are." Anyone who believes in the existence of a divine Creator will find this description of liberty as an usurpation of the prerogatives that only properly speaking pertain to God. Only God can <define> what he creates precisely because he gives his creatures all of their being. We therefore suggest that a return to a non-skeptical assessment of truth in morality is of essential importance if we hope to reach any form of common agreement as to what good moral conduct consists of. As St. John records for us, "<veritas liberabit vos>" (Jn. 8:32), the truth will set you free. One contemporary moral theologian suggests that free moral choices constitute what we <are> and what we <become>, not what we define ourselves to be.2 Perhaps the ideas of free choice and self- determination are not incompatible after all; the real problem lies in <defining> what we are and what we can or cannot licitly do as morally acting persons. What is really at issue here is the question of what exactly should it mean for us to be "pro-choice," not as it is commonly understood in "abortion-right" parlance but as a free moral act. One certainty has come to light in the abortion controversy: each human being is personally responsible for the choices they make and legal statutes should focus on the common good rather than that of the individual. Our times call for a deep work of cultural and religious formation in order to enable the individual members of society to conform their conduct, in both private and public affairs, to the laws "written" into our human nature by God. <I. Human Freedom in Light of the Casey Decision> The rather ominous quotation cited by Hittinger from Lawrence Tribe and Peter Rubin's book <Abortion: The Clash of Absolutes> (1990) is particularly revealing: "[the abortion right is the] liberty not to be moulded physically and psychologically into a mother." Although any citation taken out of context can be easily misinterpreted, in this instance, the underlying presuppositions seem to be rather obvious. Human liberty or freedom has been erected as an absolute right beyond the measure or standard of any thing or any one other than the individual <in se>. The celebrated right to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness enshrined in the Declaration of Independence, designed to protect and guarantee religious freedom, has become an exclusively individual right. It is a right which can be agreed upon by consensus but not be delineated by authority. We could interpret Tribe and Rubin's description of the "abortion right" as ascribing the power of controlling the freedom of a woman to a pre-viable fetus. Implicit here is the idea that the unborn child usurps the mother's freedom to act as she wishes, or at least it compromises her options for action. But is this really true? It could be contested that once a woman has conceived a fetus, whether viable or not <extra uterum>, she is already a mother. But using the orientation of these authors perhaps we could paraphrase the above description to read: "the potential child is a <thing>, precisely because it is incapable of voluntary human acts, a thing that alters the <personality> of a responsible human being," i.e., the potential mother. Of course most people who defend the "abortion right" would respond that it is not the fetus nor the putative father that robs a woman of her freedom but rather any legislative barriers that prevent access to abortifacient agents or abortive surgical procedures, because these restrictions deny a woman the exercise of her free choice. The most important right for a woman, they contend, is the right to terminate the only thing which can truly be given by one human being to another, <life.> Such an argument is incorrect, morally, because free choice is not directly affected by legal dictates: legislation serves to guide the good moral conduct of citizens and strives to ensure the common good of all members of society. Clearly, moral education needs legislative science, but its function is to educate and to promote the good use of our faculties as children of God. Aristotle perceived this and placed great importance on the role of the legislator and the State in contributing to the pursuit of virtue by the citizenry. He writes in the Nicomachean Ethics: "legislators should urge people toward virtue and exhort them to aim at what is fine."3 Excellent laws express the personal attention of the State for the education of the people, "for just as in cities the provisions of law and the [prevailing] types of character have influence, similarly a father's words and habits have influence, and all the more because of kinship and because of the benefits he does; for his children are already fond of him and naturally ready to obey."4 The question we propose to address here is how can a concept of human freedom, understood as unlimited personal liberty, have developed in a culture and a society which is built on the respect for the dignity of the human person? Perhaps this can be explained, at least in part, by the fact that personal dignity is not a human invention of our nation's Founding Fathers but is a revealed truth of faith. Man is created in God's image and likeness (cf. Gen. 1:26), thus man, like God, is both free and is capable of self-knowledge through his actions and his dealings with others.5 Moreover, this dignity is not only manifest in an intrinsic fashion as creatures made in God's image, but we are also intelligent beings. Therefore, we can act by way of good moral choices to attain our natural and supernatural end: happiness in this life and a hundred-fold more in the next when we act and choose according to God's will. And it is precisely the conscience which enables us to make good judgments and sound choices. Human actions are something like words through which we give ourselves an identity as moral beings; our moral character is acquired <by us> through the choices we freely make. Although it is true that we are free to choose what we do, we are not free to determine or define what we do as right or wrong. Human dignity includes the capacity to understand in some measure what God expects of us and to freely choose to relate ourselves to Him through our actions by acting and living in accord with right reason. Aristotle believed that happiness is avidly bound up with a life of reason concerned with action: man's good is his good functioning _ "the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue."6 And the best and most perfect virtue is <sophia> or understanding whose specific activity is <theoria>, contemplation.7 As Christians, we understand that our highest activity is not simply an appreciation for what is good action but that God enables us to discover what is a good action in the concrete circumstances and the moral context of each act. As a matter of fact our life is a <colloquium> with God in which we enjoy a participation in his life, "[we] participate in the light of the divine mind."8 <II. The Dignity of the Human Person> One of the most characteristic cultural traditions of our time is a heightened awareness of the inherent dignity of the human person as the authentic foundation of human freedom. Unfortunately, many of our contemporaries have forgotten, or at least they do not seem to realize, that this fact is known both by way of human reason <and> the revealed Word of God. The latter is especially important because it concerns the origin or source of human dignity and thus is important for a clear appreciation of its inherent value. The Church magisterium has discussed this "truth of man," of man's special dignity, on several occasions.9 Of particular interest for us is the Declaration, <Dignitatis humanae>, which states that "all men . . . are by their own nature impelled, and are morally bound, to seek the truth" _ "they are bound, too, to adhere to the truth they know and to order their whole life according to the requirements of the truth."10 True or sound moral judgments of conscience require that one both know and recognize the dictates of the truth. John Henry Newman pointed out, however, that this judgment of conscience is not easily performed as a disinterested operation because we can readily cede to rationalizations: "the aim of most conscientious and religious men is not how to please God, but how to please themselves without displeasing God." Another consideration we should consider is that the incarnation of the Word of God shows that man is not merely like God but that he is called to be God-like. We are constituted as beings which are essentially receptive to God's divine life; we are creatures that are made for God. In the words of St. Augustine, "you have made us for yourself, O Lord, and our hearts are restless until they rest in you."11 William May has pointed out that we find both in St. Thomas and the teachings of the Second Vatican Council that human beings possess a two-fold dignity, both being intrinsic to our <being>. One is an endowment or gift, and the other is an achievement or an acquisition.12 How then might we proceed in our discussion of good human free choice? One promising approach is a discussion on the relationship of truth to conscience.13 The personalism of John Paul II addresses the "truth about man" and suggests that it is centered on the <selfhood> of the human person. The Holy Father understands this to mean that the norms of moral conduct grow out of the truth about our personal being. Thus moral norms must be internalized and not simply applied from "outside"; we as persons are made for the truth, and we can only <live in truth> if we understand it.14 A man can be good and act well only if he is truly wise. When applied to matrimony the love present between a man and a woman is centered on their capacity for <self-donation>. And this capacity of making oneself a gift to another is founded on selfhood and the process of active self- determination through free moral acts. Although a relationship of a mother to a gestating child differs from the nuptial union of marriage, it is easy to see how the mother's act of self-donation in the marital state gives the potential child a share in her own life and the life of her spouse. The love between husband and wife serves as the context of a new creative moment by God; it is the medium of selflessness in which God communicates new life. This life is, in its deepest sense, the gift of "personhood." It is a gift that cannot be given by them but must come from God. We find ourselves face to face with the problem of how God gives a person their existence. The creative intervention of God does what we cannot do: only God can create the "person" in the context of mutual human love. According to the classical definition of the person, he/she is <sui iuris et alteri incommunicabilis>, a law unto itself and incommunicable to others. The "Law of God" is written into our personal nature <and> we cannot communicate it to another. Moreover, the willingness to bring a pre-viable life to term consolidates the initial community of love in which conception occurs.15 One might object to this "romantic" appreciation of sexual union by citing the fact that the generation of human life outside the context of marital communion is not prevented by God. There seems to be no divine provision for the authenticity of human self- donation between two persons prior to the creation of a new human life. Actually, this fact is not really a problem to our discussion but does in fact support the personalist approach to human love. In the mind of Karol Wojtyla the most radical form of human self-giving takes place between a man and a woman in the act of <spousal> love, a type of love which entails the surrender of oneself to another.16 And this spousal surrender is possible precisely because the human person is <sui iuris> (belongs to him/herself). This fact affords the possibility of <selling> oneself to another, of throwing one's "self" or "person" away in acts of love that lack the guarantee of authentic self-donation, the mark of permanent commitment. God respects our freedom so much that he does not violate the laws of nature set into motion by our free human acts. He does not prevent a bad human act even when it is an abuse of one's own self and the <person>ality of another human being. A man who simply "takes" a woman, in the absence of an authentic mutual offering of "self" performs a physical act akin to the marital one, but that act does not affect the "interiority" of either person.17 Each one remains excluded from the inner self of the other, merely using one another's physical abilities for egotistical gain. In order to appropriate the good that inheres in the other person each one must allow themselves to be known in a personal manner. This demands that the subject be open to the self of the other, and that they be willing to accept and grant full autonomy to that other self. We could say that these predisposing elements to true human love prepare each one to be receptive to the self-donation of the other and to the gift of spiritual life from God.18 Where there is no commitment of one person to another there is no authentic love, no true gift of one to the other, and thus there is no deep love for the possible resultant human life of such a union. This would in part explain why abortion on demand is so widely acclaimed in societies that do not effectively educate in the virtue of chastity and legalize marital divorce. The permanence of the family is not guaranteed by the legislative body nor is the indissolubility of the marriage bond viewed as a good but rather as an onerous burden.19 <III. Moral Acts as Self-Determining Actions> The subjectivity of human acting addresses the phenomenon of self- determination as well as that of self-awareness or self-presence. One can make a distinction between what occurs "in man" and what he/she does by way of free choices, and this is most evident to a person when they consider an action in relation to the truth, when we make judgments with the conscience.20 The attraction or power of a moral responsibility, duty, or obligation draws us out of ourselves, but it also reminds us that it is we who dispose ourselves to act in a specific manner; we determine what we are by way of our moral acting.21 Only man exists for his own sake, and the dignity of his/her selfhood is decided or determined by each person through their moral actions. For this reason we say that a human person truly determines their destiny. Our lives are not simply in the hands of blind fate or good fortune.22 Aristotle writes a principle in the soul which gives rise to both good natural desire and correct intellectual and deliberative desire, and that principle is God.23 God is a final cause for the soul, not the efficient cause. Thus man lives in obedience to the commands of the soul and not as a direct response to divine guidance. For the Philosopher God is the supreme <arche> but our intellectual faculty possesses a two- fold <arche>, one that enjoys "contact" with God and the other which is influenced by the senses and directs our actions. God does not issue commands to us but rather we command ourselves. Wisdom or understanding is the epitactic <arche> that is capable of commanding us for the sake of God and in order to serve and contemplate Him. Choices that move us to the contemplation of God are best because the Deity is the noblest criterion of judgment;