The Essential Elements of and Conditions for a "Democratic 
Republic":  The View Prevalent at the Founding and in Early 
American History

Stephen M. Krason

The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the Wilbur and Earhart 
Foundations for grants during the summers of 1985 and 1986 
respectively, which aided the researching and writing of this 
article.

Martin Diamond, Winston Mills Fisk, and Herbert Garfinkle entitled 
their American government textbook of some years ago <The 
Democratic Republic>, stating that this was the best designation 
to give to the American political order because it implies both of 
the major political principles it was intended by our Founding 
Fathers to embody.  It is "democratic" _ in the representative, 
not pure, sense _ because the majority rules; it is "republican" 
because it is supposed to demonstrate such characteristics as 
restraint, sobriety, competence, and liberty, "the very qualities 
democratic government needs to be its best self."1  This essay 
adopts their term "democratic republic" and the understanding they 
have of it.  It turns to important sources from the era of our 
Founding and in early American history generally in order to 
determine what our Founders, the political tradition they emerged 
from, and the political society of early America regarded as the 
elements and characteristics the political order had to embody and 
the social conditions which had to prevail in order to maintain a 
democratic republic.  The following sources will be examined to 
determine this:  the political philosophers John Locke and Baron 
de Montesquieu, selected early state constitutions and bills of 
rights, the writings of the Founding Fathers, and the situation 
prevailing at their time, the debates of the First Congress (which 
framed the Bill of Rights), and Alexis de Tocqueville's <Democracy 
in America.>

I. The Philosophers of Liberal Democracy:

Locke and Montesquieu

It has generally been held that Locke and Montesquieu, the key 
early modern philosophic protagonists of liberal democracy, had a 
decided influence on the American Founding.2  It is thus 
appropriate to begin by considering what they thought to be the 
essential elements and conditions for a democratic republic or 
similar regime.  It should be noted that Locke, unlike 
Montesquieu, does not write specifically about a democratic 
republic.  His <Two Treatises on Government> describe the elements 
of a <limited> government with a representative aspect, not of a 
republic <per se.>3

In Locke's <Second Treatise>, he views the state of nature as 
having been "free from any Superior Power on Earth."4  By nature a 
man has certain inalienable rights; he cannot "<enslave himself> 
to anyone, nor put himself under the Absolute, Arbitrary Power of 
another."5  The state or political order comes into existence only 
when "Men have so <consented to make one Community> or Government 
. . . and make <one Body Politick>, wherein the <Majority> have a 
Right to act and conclude the rest."6  Those who join the social 
contract establishing this new political community surrender the 
political powers they previously held to the majority, and this is 
the origin of the state's power.  Even when a particular 
government is dissolved, power still resides in the political 
community which can then turn it over to a new type of government.

Government exercises three types of power:  legislative, 
executive, and federative (the last involving the power over war-
making and foreign affairs).  Regardless of the form of 
government, Locke seems to believe that the principle of 
separation of powers must be adhered to.  He believes that, if 
otherwise, absolute arbitrary power would prevail, which men 
cannot submit to because it would violate the inalienability of 
their rights.7

Besides separation of powers and the absence of absolute, 
arbitrary power, Locke points to other elements that limited 
government (i.e., a "well-framed Government") requires.  One is 
that the supreme governmental power must reside in the 
legislature.  Locke says the following:

In all Cases, whilst the Government subsists,

the <Legislative is the Supream Power> . . . all other Powers in 
any Members or parts of the Society, derived from and subordinate 
to it . . .

The Executive Power . . . is visibly subordinate and accountable 
to it, and may be at pleasure changed and displaced . . .8

This "<Supream Power>" is the power of making laws and no 
enactment or edict can "have the force and obligation of a <Law>, 
which has not its <Sanction> from that <Legislative>, which the 
publick has chosen and appointed."9  Legislative power is by no 
means unlimited, however.  First of all, it must be recognized 
that the legislative power comes from the people _ "Men . . . put 
the Legislative Power into such hands as they think fit"10 _ and 
it was not created as an absolute power.  Locke insists that there 
are "Bounds" to legislative power set both by the original grant 
of it, in the social contract, by men and by "the Law of God and 
Nature . . . in all Forms of Government."11  Four specific limits 
which he sets out are:  that men be "govern[ed] by <promulgated 
establish'd Laws,> not to be varied in particular Cases . . . 
[and] to have one Rule for Rich and Poor"; that the "<Laws> . . . 
ought to be designed for no other end ultimately but <the good of 
the People>"12; since it is fundamental that "[t]he <Supream Power 
cannot take> from any man any part of his Property without his own 
consent,"13 it follows that it also "must <not raise taxes> on the 
Property of the People, <without the Consent of the People>, given 
by themselves, or their Deputies"; and that "[t]he <Legislative> 
neither must <nor can transfer the Power of making Laws> to any 
Body else, or place it anywhere but where the People have."14

Since men's inalienable rights preclude their establishing an 
arbitrary power over themselves, the legislature cannot act 
arbitrarily when making law.  This, in turn, suggests another 
principle of Locke's which, while not apparently mandated by him 
is certainly preferable for a commonwealth:  that those who make 
the laws must be subject to them.15

A further principle is one which seems vital to any representative 
government where the legislative is supreme:  majority rule.  This 
is logical in light of the fact that, at the time of the social 
contract, power was given to the majority.  For a governmental 
action to be valid _ Locke speaks specifically about the levying 
of taxes _ it is necessary to have "the Consent of the Majority, 
giving it either by themselves, or their Representatives chosen by 
them."16  Thus, even if Locke is not seeking to set forth 
principles for a representative <democracy> or a democratic 
republic, <per se,> by emphasizing such a majority-rule principle 
he clearly builds a fundamental democratic component into his 
notion of the well-ordered commonwealth.

Tied in with the limitation on the legislature of making laws only 
for the good of the people is another, more fundamental, Lockean 
principle that the "well-framed government" must exhibit:  the end 
of the government must be the good of the community.  Whatever 
"alterations are made in it, tending to that end, cannot be an 
<incroachment> upon any body."17

Locke sets forth one other noteworthy principle:  the right of 
revolution.  He says that when someone _ he was writing, of 
course, particularly with reference to the English kings before 
the Glorious Revolution _ tries to make laws "whom the People have 
not appointed so to do," the laws have no force and the people 
have no obligation to obey.  They may resist the usurpers of 
legislative authority "and may constitute to themselves a <new 
Legislative>."18  This "<new Legislative>" can be of the nature of 
a "change of Persons, or Form, or both."19

In summary, then, we can say that the following are the elements 
and principles Locke saw as necessary for limited government and, 
logically, for a democratic republic:  the absence of arbitrary, 
absolute power; separation of powers; political power must be 
understood as being derived from the people; laws must be firmly 
in place, adequately promulgated, and applicable to all; laws must 
be designed for the good of the people and the end of government, 
generally, must be understood as being the good of the community; 
property cannot be taken from nor taxes levied upon men without 
their, or their representatives', consent; the legislature cannot 
transfer the power of making laws; those who make the laws must be 
subject to them; majority rule must prevail; and the right of 
revolution exists whenever someone who does not have the authority 
to do so tries to seize the legislative power in the community.

In his key work, <The Spirit of the Laws>, Montesquieu devotes 
much attention to the elements necessary to maintain a democratic 
republic.20  A number of the principles he puts forth are the same 
or similar to Locke's:  the people should be supreme and have the 
sole power to enact laws, they must be able to choose their 
magistrates, and separation of powers is needed.21

He also sets forth principles involving suffrage, which is the way 
the people exercise their sovereignty.22  The citizens must be 
able to fix those of their number who are to form the public 
assemblies."23  (He apparently is thinking here of something like 
the direct democracy which existed in ancient Greece, although the 
principle expressed would seem applicable to a larger democratic 
republic in the sense of the people being permitted to decide how 
many citizens should have the vote.)

He also advocates suffrage by lot in choosing magistrates, a 
practice which he says is "natural to democracy."  That is, those 
who will be among the candidates for election as magistrates 
should be chosen by lot from among the eligible electorate, or 
from certain classes in the electorate.  This, when modified to 
insure that the people chosen are worthy, will motivate the desire 
of citizens to serve their country.  He contends also that to have 
suffrages in public instead of secret (i.e., people stating who 
they are voting for) is "a fundamental law of democracy."  The 
early American practice of viva voce elections followed this 
principle.  The reason for this is that "[t]he lower class ought 
to be directed by those of a higher rank and [be] restrained 
within bounds by eminent personages."24

Montesquieu also pointed to a number of moral and social 
conditions that had to prevail in a democratic republic.  The 
first of these is, simply, the need for virtue.  This is much more 
crucial in a republic than in either a monarchical or despotic 
government, where the "force of laws" and the "prince's arm," 
respectively, "are sufficient to direct and maintain the whole."25  
Montesquieu defines this virtue as "the love of the laws and of 
our country," and says that it entails "a constant preference of 
public to private interest," and adopting of "good maxims" to 
direct people's lives, and a love of equality and frugality.26  
Connected with the latter is the need to maintain a fixed and 
certain credit.27

In addition to promoting a love of equality, a republic must also 
divide its land equally among its citizens, and also insure that 
the divisions be small.  He also calls for an "equality of 
fortunes," saying that this supports frugality."28  He does not 
insist upon a rigid, strict equality of either land or fortunes, 
however, merely a relative one.  He says that "[a]n equal division 
of lands cannot be established in all democracies . . . [and in] 
some circumstances . . . would be impracticable, dangerous, and 
even subversive of the constitution"29 and that "[d]emocracy has . 
. . two excesses to avoid _ the spirit of inequality . . . and the 
spirit of extreme equality, which leads to despotic power."30  In 
"a well-regulated democracy," equality extends only to men as 
citizens (i.e., in the rights and duties of citizenship), not to 
their other associations and relationships (i.e., it does not 
extend to men "as magistrates, as senators, as judges, as fathers, 
as husbands, or as masters").31

As equality must be limited, so must liberty.  It must be 
understood that it involves not only the freedom to <do> certain 
things, but also the freedom to live safely in the midst of 
others.32  Thus, he defines liberty as "a right of doing whatever 
the laws permit" and seems to confine it to the realm of the 
political.33

Three other social conditions must prevail for a democratic 
republic, two of which involve the virtue mentioned above.  
Education is needed to instill virtue (this "ought to be the 
principal business of education")34 with the aim of producing wise 
men to govern.  He also insists, contrary to the Founding Fathers, 
that the overall territory of a republic must be small.35

II. Early State Constitutions and Bills of Rights

Another source to turn to for our inquiry are the provisions of 
state constitutions and bills of rights.  These are especially 
valuable because, since they represent the establishment of the 
fundamental law of a state, they are illustrative of a basic 
political consensus.  They are limited, however, as a source of 
information because, while containing statements of basic 
principles of political philosophy and institutional provisions 
which suggest such principles, they also contain many technical 
provisions about the carrying out of various governmental 
activities which are not especially enlightening for our purpose.  
No attempt will be made here to examine in detail state 
constitutions of the period, although a brief, general survey of 
state bills of rights follows in order to point out the rights 
most widely accepted at the time of our Founding.  Rather, the 
constitutions of two large, important states at the time of our 
Founding are considered:  Virginia and Massachusetts.

The most noteworthy political principles contributed by Virginia 
to the American Founding are seen in the Virginia Bill of Rights 
of 1776, which we shall consider shortly.  Three significant ideas 
appear in Virginia's Constitution of 1776, however:  separation of 
powers, rotation of officeholders (referring specifically to the 
state legislature) and a generally limited duration of office, and 
the need to maintain fixed and adequate salaries of state 
judges.36

The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780, which succeeded the 
charters of the Massachusetts Bay Colony, is a much longer 
document and embodies many more basic political principles than 
the Virginia Constitution of 1776.  It states or implies the 
following principles:  separation of powers; that there must be 
"an equitable mode of making laws, as well as . . . an impartial 
interpretation and a faithful execution of them"37; free 
elections; frequent elections for both legislative and 
international office (it specifically calls for annual elections); 
the need for a landed electorate; election of the legislative 
branch on the basis of "the principle of equality," which means 
appointment of legislative seats on the basis of the number of 
electors paying poll tax; election by written _ and, it follows by 
implication _ secret ballot; that laws should not be suspended; 
the requirement of money bills originating in the house of 
representatives; the protection of members of the legislature from 
arrest or process while attending or traveling to or from the 
legislative session; and the need for holders of executive offices 
(governor and lieutenant governor) to meet religious 
qualifications (the governor is specifically required to be a 
Christian).38

The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780 makes some general 
statements of political philosophy, both in its Preamble and in 
its section which lists the rights of the Commonwealth's 
inhabitants (the "bill of rights" was a part of the body of the 
document; there was no separate bill of rights as in Virginia's 
case).  No statements of political philosophy appear in the 
Virginia Constitution; they are in the Virginia Bill of Rights.  
We turn to these passages now.

The Virginia Bill of Rights, like the Massachusetts Constitution, 
makes a statement about the natural liberty and inherent rights of 
men.  The former says that "all men are by nature equally free and 
independent, and have certain inherent rights, of which, when they 
enter into a state of society, they cannot, by any compact, 
deprive or divest their posterity . . ."39  The latter states that 
"[a]ll men are born free and equal, and have certain natural, 
essential, and unalienable rights . . ."40  Both list these 
"inherent" or "unalienable" rights:  enjoying life and liberty, 
acquiring and protecting property, and seeking and obtaining 
happiness and safety.  The Massachusetts Constitution, perhaps 
reflecting the origins of the colony in the Mayflower Compact, 
speaks of the origins of the "body-politic" in a "social compact."  
The Virginia Bill of Rights makes only an indirect reference to 
such a compact in the above passage.  The latter affirms that 
political power is derived from the people and that their 
magistrates are answerable to them.  Both hold that the purpose of 
government is to help individuals secure the natural rights above 
and to promote the common good, and if it fails to do this the 
people may alter or abolish it.  The Massachusetts Constitution 
insists also that all men have the obligation to worship God and 
it asks for His direction of the government it is creating.  It 
also acknowledges that "the happiness of a people and the good 
order and preservation of civil government essentially depend upon 
piety, religion, and morality."41

The Virginia Bill of Rights also contains a statement of 
additional specific governmental principles and practices besides 
those in the Constitution (apart from the specific guarantees of 
individual rights).  These are that no emoluments ought to be 
given men by the community except in return for services, that no 
offices by hereditary, that elections be frequent (this is really 
just an elaboration about the points concerning duration of office 
in the body of the Constitution), that elections be free, that 
electors have "permanent common interest with, and attachment to, 
the community," that the people cannot be bound by any law or tax 
levy not consented to by themselves or their representatives, and 
that laws cannot be suspended or executed without the people's 
consent.42

The political thought of early America, built in part on a Lockean 
base, believed that one of the most, if not <the> most, 
fundamental purpose of government is to secure man's rights.  
Which rights appeared most frequently in state constitutions and 
bills of rights, and thereby were probably viewed as most 
essential to a democratic republic?  All of the early state bills 
of rights guaranteed the right of a jury trial, freedom of the 
press, and that the accused be informed of the charge against him.  
The protection of life, liberty, and property _ already alluded to 
as having been mentioned in the Virginia and Massachusetts 
documents _ was the next most frequent guarantee.  Related to this 
was the specific guarantee of <habeas corpus>, which Massachusetts 
and Georgia guaranteed.  Six states required that persons accused 
of crimes be permitted to have witnesses in their behalf.  General 
warrants were forbidden by five states, the same number which 
granted protection from self-incrimination.  Five states also 
forbade cruel and unusual punishments and prohibited the exaction 
of excessive bail.  Three other states besides Virginia and 
Massachusetts provided that laws not be suspended.  Four states 
prohibited <ex post facto> laws and (in the words of the Magna 
Carta) provided that justice not be sold, denied or delayed.43

Other rights found their way into a smaller number of state 
constitutions and bills of rights.  These were the following:  
guarantees against double jeopardy and being held for an infamous 
crime without indictment or presentment of a grand jury; the 
disallowance of bills of attainder; the guarantee that private 
property not be taken for public use without compensation; the 
right to emigrate to another state; the impartiality or 
independence of judges; the barring of the quartering of soldiers 
in private homes in time of peace; the forbidding of monopolies; 
the guarantee that citizens will enjoy common law rights; the 
requirement that penalties be proportionate to the offense; the 
guarantee that the military was to be strictly subordinated to the 
civil power; the requirement _ stated above as a general 
governmental principle found in the Massachusetts Constitution of 
1780 _ that taxes be levied only with legislative consent; the 
right of counsel to accused persons; protection against 
unreasonable searches and seizures; the right to bear arms, 
freedom of religion, the right to assemble and petition.44

We can reasonably conclude that the rights that appear most 
frequently in the various early state constitutions and bills of 
rights would be judged to have been viewed as the most essential 
to a democratic republic.  Nevertheless, all the rights mentioned 
above except the right to emigrate, the forbidding of monopolies, 
the guarantee of common law rights, the proportionality of 
penalties, and the subordination of the military to the civil 
power were adopted, in some form, by either the federal 
Constitution or Bill of Rights.  Arguably, even these latter were 
implicitly adopted.  The first two are perhaps implied in the 
privileges and immunities clause of the Constitution, the third in 
the Ninth Amendment, the fourth in the Eighth Amendment, and the 
fifth in the Third Amendment and the entire idea behind the U.S. 
Constitution.  It even <added> such provisions as the inclusive 
due process clause found in the Fifth Amendment and the Seventh 
Amendment guaranteed that facts found by a jury could not be 
reexamined except according to the practice of the common law.

Even though the federal Constitution and Bill of Rights emerged as 
an almost all-inclusive statement of the political rights of 
Americans, we can judge from the discussion above that in the 
years leading up to the adoption of the federal Bill of Rights by 
the First Congress _ which really must be viewed as an extension 
of the Founders' work on the Constitution since many were also in 
the first Congress _ that some of the rights were viewed as more 
essential or basic than others.  This is reinforced by the debate 
in the First Congress.  During that debate, Madison singled out 
for mention the rights of conscience (i.e., freedom of religion), 
freedom of speech, press freedom, and trial by jury.  He suggested 
these were the preeminent rights.  Other members of the first 
House of Representatives during the debate singled out certain 
other rights in such a manner as to lead to the conclusion that 
they believed them to be the most basic and necessary.  These were 
<habeas corpus,> freedom of religion, freedom of speech and 
assembly, and (in the words of one representative) the "rights 
granted to the [British] subject."  The latter would seem to refer 
primarily to trial by jury of one's peers, <habeas corpus>, and 
various due process guarantees.45

In spite of this clear basis for asserting that the Founding 
Fathers and the American political society of their time and the 
years before it viewed certain rights as more important, the 
enactment of the Bill of Rights, as it stands, can be understood 
as an acceptance of almost all of the above rights as "necessary" 
and basic for a democratic republic, or at least that they should 
be viewed as such from that point forward.

III. The Views of the Founding Fathers and the Political Society 
of their Time

We shall now consider the Founding Fathers' views and the thinking 
generally prevalent in their time _ as put forth directly in 
important writings or as seen implicitly in political practices _ 
about the principles and elements that had to characterize a 
democratic republic and the conditions necessary to maintain it.  
We shall first note the ideas most widely prevalent in their 
political society about this, then the ideas put forth by the most 
eminent of the Founders and others who were particularly active or 
influential at the 1787 Constitutional Convention.46

Two historians of the politics of colonial America, Bernard Bailyn 
and George Dargo, mention a number of commonly held principles of 
this sort before the Revolution.  Bailyn says that it was "almost 
an axiom of political thought in eighteenth century America" that 
the colonial legislatures were replicas, albeit imperfect, of 
England's "mixed and balanced constitution."  In fact, however, 
the colonial notion of a mixed constitution deviated from the 
Mother Country's in one fundamental way, the fact that there was 
no traditional aristocracy, the "middle order" in England, which 
kept the "extremes of power and liberty from tearing each other 
apart," and in many lesser ones, such as refusing a permanent 
salary to colonial executives.47

Later, after independence, the early state constitutions 
introduced ideas and structures which suggested the notion of 
separation of powers.  Bailyn, however, contends that they really 
derive from this English idea of the mixed constitution, not from 
the idea of balancing the functions of branches of government, and 
from a belief that government faced dangers from "influence" and 
"corruption."48  In fact, Dargo tells us that, instead of 
emphasizing separation of powers, "[t]he colonial experience had 
pointed toward a system of <legislative supremacy.">49  This is 
not surprising, in light of the long colonial struggles against 
the arbitrary power of colonial governors appointed by the Crown.  
Ultimately, of course, legislative supremacy was rejected and what 
came to be accepted emerged as the cornerstone principle of 
American government:  "separation of powers, mixed with an 
elaborate system of checks and balances among roughly equal 
branches . . ."50  By the mid-eighteenth century, "separation of 
powers" had assumed its modern meaning that the functions of 
government were to be kept apart by separating the agencies, or 
departments, that performed these functions and by barring the 
personnel of one from serving simultaneously in another.  In 
practice, however, legislative supremacy continued until after the 
ratification of the federal Constitution.51

The other principles that Bailyn and Dargo point to as 
characterizing early American political thought and practice are 
freedom of speech,52 an independent judiciary,53 a broad 
franchise,54 representation corresponding with population 
levels,55 equitable apportionment,56 and the beginnings of the 
Madisonian view of factions and political parties.57

Some brief elaboration on the latter four points is in order.  On 
the subject of the franchise, Bailyn states that as a 
generalization in the colonies as a whole, "it seems safe to say 
that fifty to seventy-five per cent of the adult male white 
population was entitled to vote _ far more than could do so in 
England . . ."58  He says that representation kept up with 
expanding populations and that apportionment, by eighteenth 
century standards, was "remarkably equitable, well adjusted to the 
growth and spread of population . . ."59

Bailyn states the following about the view of parties and factions 
in America before the second quarter of the eighteenth century:

Parties and factions _ their destructiveness, the history of the 
evils they brought upon mankind, their significance as symptoms of 
disease in the body politic _ are endlessly condemned and 
endlessly abjured.60

In the 1730s, however, the view began to change.  One New York 
writer states that "some opposition, though it proceed not 
entirely from a public spirit, is not only necessary in free 
governments but of great service to the public.  Parties are a 
check upon one another, and by keeping the ambition of one another 
within bounds, serve to maintain the public liberty."  A 
Pennsylvanian writes that "there can be no liberty without 
faction."  Sporadically, this new perspective surfaced in American 
political writings during the middle fifty years of the eighteenth 
century until it was fully elaborated by Madison in Federalist 
10.61

What Madison says in Federalist 10 becomes, of course, standard 
American thought at the time of the drafting of the Constitution.  
He says that since the "mischiefs of faction" cannot be cured by 
removing its causes _ this would require actually destroying 
liberty or performing the task rendered impossible by human nature 
of giving everyone the same opinions, passions, and interests _ it 
is necessary to try to control its effects.  This is done in the 
following ways:  if the faction is less than a majority, the 
"republican principle" enables the majority to defeat it simply by 
a vote; if the faction includes a majority, popular government 
must render its members "unable to concert and carry into effect 
schemes of oppression."  It does the latter by means of the 
"extensive republic," which has the result both of providing a 
larger pool of capable, virtuous citizens from which to choose 
representatives, of making cabals less likely because of the vast 
territory, and of increasing and diversifying the number of 
parties and interests making it less likely that a power-clutching 
majority will develop.62

Separation of powers has already been mentioned as a principal 
tenet of early American political thought.  The Founding Fathers, 
of course, also installed it into the Constitution.  The 
Constitution does not explicitly endorse the principle, but it is 
clearly built into the structure and proposed functioning of the 
federal government by the enumerated duties and prerogatives of 
each of the branches.  The importance of separation of powers is 
emphasized in the writings of several of the Founders; in fact, it 
can fairly be said to be for them the primary structural or 
operational principle of government.  Hamilton, for example, 
defines "despotism" as a government in which all power is 
concentrated in a single body.63  John Dickinson writes that 
government must never be lodged in a single body.64  Edmund 
Randolph, a delegate at the Convention who first opposed the 
Constitution then later defended it, also emphasizes the 
importance of separation of powers in his writing,65 as does 
Madison in Federalist 476 who says about it that "No political 
truth is certainly of greater intrinsic value."66  Jefferson, of 
course, was not at the Convention, but his influence on the 
shaping of American political thought give him not only a place, 
but a prominent one, among our Founding Fathers.  The centrality 
of separation of powers in his thinking is clearly seen in his 
proposed constitutions for Virginia in 1776 and 1783.67

The other essential element of a democratic republic listed most 
frequently by the Founders in their writings is the guarantee of 
certain rights.  Jefferson stresses particularly freedom of press 
and religion, but mentions also other rights and insists on a bill 
of rights in his correspondence with Madison about the proposed 
Constitution.68  Madison speaks of freedom of speech and press and 
property rights.69  James Wilson emphasized liberty of the 
press.70  The Federalist makes reference specifically to trial by 
jury, freedom of the press, and the constitutional provision 
against bills of attainder.  The fact, as we have already seen, 
that all the original thirteen states had bills of rights or 
otherwise built guarantees into their constitutions indicates the 
widespread belief at the Founding that protecting political rights 
was seen as a crucial role of republican government.  The only 
real dispute regarding government and citizen rights at the time 
of the Founding, of course, concerned a federal bill of rights.  
There was probably little doubt that a primary purpose of the 
federal as well as state governments _ as affirmed by the Preamble 
of the Constitution which speaks of "secur[ing] the blessing of 
liberty" and by the Declaration of Independence, which must also 
be viewed as one of our Founding documents _ was the defense of 
individual rights.  The main point in the controversy between the 
Federalists and Anti-Federalists was not whether the rights 
existed or should be protected, but simply whether they needed to 
be enunciated in a federal bill of rights as they already were in 
state ones.

There are many other principles that the more prominent of our 
Founding Fathers enunciated in their writings as being important 
in a democratic republic.  We might place these principles into 
four categories:  institutional features of the government, 
aspects of democratic practice not specifically relating to 
governmental institutions, the conducting of government, and moral 
and social conditions necessary to sustain a democratic republic.

A number of the principles in the institutional category are 
related to the notion of separation of powers.  For example, John 
Adams writes in his Defence of the importance of "mixed 
government," by which he meant both the Lockean idea of the 
functional division among different branches and the older, 
Aristotelian notion of different social and economic classes being 
represented in and balanced off in government.  He contended that 
birth, fortune, and property should all be considered in the 
governments of the various American states _ indeed, property 
should be represented in the legislatures _ but that "merit should 
be preferred."  A mixed government, where political power is 
divided among different branches, is more likely to acknowledge 
merit than one where there is only one repository of power; there, 
"it has three resources, one in each branch of the legislature, 
and a fourth in the courts of justice."  Connected with Adams' 
conception of mixed government is another principle which has 
significance both for this Aristotelian notion and the modern idea 
of separation of powers:  that the "people's house" of the 
legislature should have equal power as the senate and have a 
genuine check on it.  This, of course, was embodied in the U.S. 
Constitution with the House and Senate being co-equal branches.  
While a people's house is needed in a mixed government to protect 
the poor, an "executive power, vested with a negative" [a veto] is 
needed to protect the propertied.71

Madison and Hamilton echo some of these same points in their 
arguments in support of the federal Constitution of 1787.  They 
say that a senate _ an institution identified with stability 
because it is not so subject to popular pressures _ is needed to 
prevent, in Madison's words, the "infirmities of popular 
government."72  Hamilton emphasizes that both a Senate and a 
popular assembly are essential:  "balance and mutual control [are] 
indispensable to a wise administration."73  The importance of "a 
broad democratic branch" cannot be overstated, according to 
Hamilton, because "[i]n free republics . . . the will of the 
people makes the essential principle of government."  There must 
be, however, "mutual checks" among the branches, and, in general, 
legislative power must be limited.74

Another institutional principle relating to the division of powers 
which is emphasized by such Founders as Adams, Jefferson, and, in 
Federalist 78, Hamilton is the need for an independent judiciary.  
The Founders, of course, did not elaborate much on the structure 
or powers of the judiciary except that, if we are to judge from 
Federalist 78, they believed it, by nature, had less power than 
either the legislative or the executive because it "has no 
influence over either the sword or the purse; no direction either 
of the strength or the wealth of the society; and can take no 
active resolution whatever."75

Hamilton, representing the view of the majority at the 
Constitutional Convention, speaks of two other essential 
institutional principles for a democratic republic, or at least 
the American democratic republic:  a maintenance of the strength 
of state governments and a preservation of a balance of power 
between them and the federal government (in other words, the 
principle of federalism), and a strong union ("a firm union is as 
necessary to perpetuate our liberties as it is to make us 
respectable").76

I am placing under the category of "democratic practice" those 
political principles and practices which do not pertain to the 
institutional arrangements of government but to the means of 
insuring that there is popular participation in the government and 
that it is responsible to the popular will.  A number of these 
principles and practices pertain to voting.  On this subject, 
there were some differences among the most eminent Framers, but we 
still can perceive a consensus about basic aspects of this 
question.  Adams and Jefferson both assert the need to have 
certain qualifications for voting, property among them.  Adams' 
scheme of mixed government called, of course, for propertied 
interests along with persons of high birth and considerable 
fortune to be represented in the government, specifically in the 
senate.  He does not mention requirements for voting for the 
popular assembly in his writings; if he favored any they would 
presumably be considerably broad.  Jefferson speaks of 
qualifications, but he is not insistent on one for property.  In 
his 1783 draft of a constitution for Virginia, for example, he 
stipulates that all free male citizens who have reached the age of 
majority, are sane, and have either resided in their county for at 
least one year, possessed real property in it of a certain value, 
or have been enrolled in the militia shall be permitted to vote 
for the legislature.77  Jefferson thus believed that to vote a man 
had to give evidence of some ongoing attachment to the community, 
although this did not have to be established by real property 
ownership.  Madison, on the other hand, is opposed to a property 
qualification for voting, even while acknowledging that government 
must be concerned about protecting property rights.  He says that 
"[c]onfining the right of suffrage to freeholders, and to such as 
hold an equivalent property, convertible . . . into freeholds . . 
. violates the vital principle of free Government that those who 
are to be bound by the laws ought to have a voice in making 
them."78  He also opposes Adams' idea of one branch for property 
holders and the other for those without property, saying that 
instead property might be protected by enlarging election 
districts for one branch and extending the term of office for that 
branch (the solution which, by and large, was adopted at the 
Constitutional Convention).  He also suggests that it would be in 
keeping with the nature of our political order for us to have 
"equal and universal suffrage," if experience or public opinion 
ultimately should require it.79

Probably Madison stands in a minority on the right of suffrage, 
both in light of the thinking of his fellow Framers and the 
general practice of his time.  Property, or at least some 
attachment to the community, was seen as a necessary requirement.  
This is a clear-cut example of the Founders putting a limit on 
popular rule and recognizing, in the Constitution, the need for a 
balancing of interests.  The Convention, in a sense, accepted 
Madison's view as a principle of the national government by not 
setting any requirements but leaving the regulation of the 
franchise to the states.  Madison's view represents, however, a 
recognition by the Framers of something Tocqueville later 
discussed:  the likelihood of pressures for the increasing 
democratization of the American political order.

Another aspect of democratic practice, often linked in the 
Framers' writings with the right of suffrage, is duration in 
office.  There seems to have been a view prevalent among the 
Framers and in the American political society of their time that 
terms of office should be short _ except for the branch 
representing property, the senate _ and elections should be 
frequent.80  Except, again, for the senate, offices should be 
filled by popular election, which Hamilton says is "the most 
unbounded liberty allowed."81

The latter point about popular election is an expression of a much 
more basic principle, which has been indirectly alluded to above, 
which permeated the thinking of the Founders and of the political 
society of America in their time:  popular sovereignty.  We can 
see this principle stated directly in a number of their writings 
and speeches.  There is no doubt, as Diamond, Fisk, and Garfinkle 
state, the political philosophy behind the American Constitution 
is a democratic one,82 contrary to the arguments of some twentieth 
century scholars and writers.83  Thus, Jefferson writes that the 
"mother principle" of democratic republics must be that "they 
embody the will of their people and execute it" and says of the 
notion of popular control of our government through elected 
representatives that we must "bring to the test of this canon 
every branch of our constitution."84  Hamilton insists there be 
free and fixed representation based on pure and equal 
principles.85  Madison contends that "the vital principle of 
republican government is the <lex majoris partis>, the will of the 
majority."86  John Adams insisted that "the people's fair, full, 
and honest consent, to every law, by the representatives, must be 
made an essential part of their constitution."87  George 
Washington said, "The basis of our political systems is the right 
of the people to make and to alter their constitutions of 
government."88  Edmund Randolph maintains that a free government 
is one in which "laws [are] made with the assent of the people."89

The above dimension of the idea of popular sovereignty concerns 
the actions and policy of government proceeding along democratic 
lines.  Another dimension was seen clearly in the emphasis placed 
on individual rights, which is clear from what has already been 
discussed.  The general principle governing the latter was 
enunciated by Jefferson:  "The true foundation of republican 
government is the equal right of every citizen, in his person and 
property, and in their management."90  In a similar vein, 
Jefferson says that "though the will of the majority is in all 
cases to prevail, it must be reasonable" and "the minority possess 
their equal rights, which equal laws must protect . . ."91

Two other aspects of democratic practice connected with the 
principle of popular sovereignty which are stressed in the 
writings of a number of Framers are that taxation cannot be levied 
without the consent of the people's representatives _ and, more 
generally, that the state's power to tax is not unlimited _ and 
that there be civilian control of the military regulated by the 
laws.92

Two other principles that could be placed, although perhaps not 
precisely, into the category of "democratic practice" are put 
forth by John Adams.  The first is that the laws are preeminent in 
a democratic republic.  He says:  "the laws . . . are the only 
possible rule, measure, and security of justice"93 and "alone can 
be trusted with unlimited confidence."94  The second is that the 
laws must embody the natural and divine laws.95

A number of points, which Washington and Jefferson enunciate, fall 
into the category of the conducting of government.  These 
represent their views about practices which had to be followed by 
the statesmen at the helm of the American government if it is to 
remain a democratic republic.  The first of these is that the 
national government must have "energy" or "vigor."  Both 
Washington and Jefferson seem to see this as something grounded in 
the institutional framework of our government _ in the 
Constitution _ but realized in the continuing practice and action 
of our statesmen.96  This theme of an "energetic" or "vigorous" 
national government being needed is also seen in such Hamilton-
composed Federalist papers as 23, 25, and 70.97

Washington and Jefferson also put forth points about government 
expenditures and the public debt, which are particularly worth 
noting at this time when this is a subject of so much public 
discussion.  Washington, in his famous Farewell Address, instructs 
his countrymen to, "[a]s a very important source of strength and 
security, cherish public credit."  He proposes two practices to 
accomplish this:  using public credit "as sparingly as possible" 
and avoiding the accumulation of debt.98  Jefferson, in his First 
Inaugural Address, recommends these practices:  "economy in the 
public expense, that labor may be lightly burdened" and "the 
honest payment of our debts and sacred preservation of the public 
faith."99  In a later letter, he emphasizes that perpetual 
government debt can interfere with liberty:  "We must make our 
election between <economy and liberty or profusion and servitude.>  
This is because taxation follows debts, "and in its train 
wretchedness and oppression."100

Another related point that Jefferson stresses is that the 
government should undertake policies which promote or assist the 
economy.  It should encourage agriculture and commerce as its 
"handmaid."101

Both Washington and Jefferson enunciate a number of other 
principles which relate to the military and foreign affairs.  As 
stated above, civilian control of the military is one of these.  
Another, according to Jefferson, is "a well-disciplined 
militia."102  Washington insists that we must avoid "overgrown 
military establishments which under any form of government are 
inauspicious to liberty . . ."103  As far as foreign affairs is 
concerned, Washington cautioned the nation about the dangers of 
foreign influence and of "[e]xcessive partiality for one foreign 
nation and excessive dislike for another."104  His administration 
is remembered for putting these principles into practice in its 
policy of neutrality between England and France.

Jefferson adds one other principle involving the conduct of 
government:  "the diffusion of information and the arraignment of 
all abuses at the bar of public reason."105  What he seems to mean 
by this is that the conduct of government must essentially be in 
the open, not secret or hidden from public view.  This will 
prevent abuse or permit it to be exposed and corrected by the 
force of public opinion.

Let us now turn to the fourth category of principles enunciated by 
the Founding Fathers, those relating to moral and social 
conditions necessary for free government.  The first of these is 
respect for the government on the part of its people and an 
obedience and reverence for its laws.106  Adams, as noted above, 
said that the laws must be preeminent in a democratic republic; 
there must be the rule of law.  If there is to be the rule of law, 
however, there must be something more than even respect or 
obedience for them; indeed, there must be reverence.  Adams links 
this with virtue in the citizenry, the second condition emphasized 
by the Founders which can be pointed to.  He says the following:  
"that form of government which unites all the virtue, honor, and 
fear of the citizens, in a reverence and obedience to the laws, is 
the only one in which liberty can be secure and all . . . [made] 
to prefer the public good before their own."107

Jefferson and Madison say that something still further is required 
in the minds and hearts of the people besides reverence for the 
laws:  a spirit of commitment to republican principles.108  
Madison speaks of "the vigilant and manly spirit which actuates 
the people of America."  The spirit "nourishes freedom, and in 
return is nourished by it."109

The importance of virtue, both for the citizenry and for political 
leaders, is also stressed by other Framers.  Jefferson writes that 
the people are to be trusted so long as they remain virtuous, a 
condition which he believes will prevail "as long as agriculture 
is our principal object"110 (this no doubt accounts for his belief 
in his later First Inaugural Address that it is essential that 
free governments encourage agriculture).  Hamilton _ in effect, 
enunciating a prime principle of the new system of government _ 
maintains that free government requires that a people have 
"strongly connected the virtue of . . . [their] rulers with their 
[the rulers'] interest."111  In other words, the political leaders 
must be made to see _ the political order must be fashioned to 
motivate this _ that acting virtuously is in their interest.  
Virtue, then, is one of the factors the Founding Fathers believed 
necessary for insuring both respect for the government and laws 
and a republican spirit.

The Framers believed that education, religion and morality, in 
addition to virtue, were needed to shape respect for the 
government, reverence for laws, republican spirit, etc.  The 
importance of education for a democratic republic appears 
frequently in Jefferson's writings.  For example, the Bill for the 
More General Diffusion of Knowledge, drafted by Jefferson in 
Virginia in 1779, endorses education as the means of preventing 
even the best forms of government from degenerating into 
tyranny.112  He viewed moral education113 and a form of 
citizenship education as the means by which people in a republic, 
specifically, could be made to see that "it is in their interest 
to preserve peace and order."114  Madison speaks of "[l]earned 
institutions" throwing "that light over the public mind which is 
the best security against crafty and dangerous encroachments on 
the public liberty."115  Washington similarly encourages the 
development of such institutions, saying that "[i]n proportion as 
the structure of a government gives force to public opinion, it is 
essential that public opinion should be enlightened."116  John 
Adams states that to preserve a democratic republic, "[c]hildren 
should be educated and instructed in the principles of freedom."  
He insists that "[e]ducation is more indispensable, and must be 
more general, under a free government than any other . . . In a 
government of three branches, they hope to be called to public 
service, where it is necessary."117

A particularly direct acknowledgement of the need for religion and 
morality comes from Washington in his "Farewell Address":

Of all the dispositions and habits which lead to political 
prosperity, religion and morality are indispensable supports.  In 
vain would that man claim the tribute of patriotism, who should 
labor to subvest these great pillars of human 

happiness, these firmest props of the duties of men and 
citizens.118

Jefferson, in a famous letter to John Adams late in his life, 
pointed to another social condition which he believed is required 
by a democratic republic:  a natural aristoi of virtue.  He writes 
this:

The natural aristocracy I consider as the most precious gift of 
nature . . . for the government of society . . . May we not even 
say, that that form of government is the best, which provides the 
most effectively for a pure selection of these natural aristoi 
into the offices of government?119

He does not talk, as Hamilton does, about this group of persons 
destined to be leaders having to be shown that acting virtuously 
is in their own best interest.  The virtue is there already; that 
is, it is "natural" or present because the people have a natural 
inclination to it and have worked to develop it.  This type of 
aristocracy, however, is not incompatible with republican 
government as the old hereditary aristocracy was (Jefferson calls 
the latter "artificial aristocracy").  Republican government, 
rather, <makes it possible> because free elections are needed to 
bring it forth to separate this natural aristocracy from the 
artificial.120  (There is thus a symbiotic relationship between 
the natural aristoi and republican government.  While the latter 
is needed to bring it forth, it is Jefferson's whole point in this 
letter that republican government needs this natural aristoi to 
thrive.)

IV. The Observations of Tocqueville About the Essential Principles 
and Conditions for a Democratic Republic

In this final section, we consider the observations of one of the 
great students and commentators of the American political and 
social orders, Alexis de Tocqueville, about our subject.  Studying 
Tocqueville enables us to point to the views about the essential 
principles and conditions for a democratic republic which 
prevailed in the United States of a generation or so after the 
Founding Fathers.  Examining this period is useful because it is 
still close enough to our Founding for the original principles and 
ideas to have retained their integrity and vitality and also is a 
time by which substantial experience had been gotten in putting 
these principles into practice.  Since Tocqueville's discussion in 
<Democracy in America> is of the attitudes and principles of the 
political society he observes and of his conclusions after 
examining it _ as opposed to being simply an expounding of his own 
political philosophy _ it is a good source for us.

Tocqueville's observations about the essential principles and 
conditions can be divided into three categories:  geographical, 
political, and _ the most numerous _ social-economic.  Tocqueville 
singles out two geographical factors:  the vast, empty, 
uncultivated land that Americans were still exploring in his time 
and the great natural resources available.  He makes clear, 
however, that this is only a minor factor in maintaining a 
democratic republic, as evidenced by the fact that South America 
has the same desirable natural circumstances but has not succeeded 
in this.  He suggests, particularly, that this natural abundance 
helps maintain American democracy because it provides prosperity, 
which in turn insures democratic laws.121

As far as political factors are concerned, Tocqueville mentions 
the following (most of which are institutional):  the federal 
system of government (which he calls "one of the most powerful 
combinations favoring human prosperity and freedom");122 the way 
the judicial power is organized in the U.S. (he refers 
specifically to such limits upon the judiciary as being able to 
pronounce upon the validity of a law only with reference to a 
particular case, making decisions only "on particular cases and 
not on general principles," being able to act only when called 
upon, and being subject to the Constitution like other political 
actors and citizens),123 good laws;124 the existence of "communal 
institutions," which "moderate the despotism of the majority and 
give the people both a taste for freedom and the skill to be free" 
(by "communal institutions," he apparently means legislative 
bodies and the like),125 and the fact that the U.S. then had "no 
great capital," which he says would result in the destinies of a 
whole country being placed in the hands of only a "section of the 
people . . . acting on their own."126

It is, essentially, the practical effects of the federal system 
that Tocqueville is referring to in the section of <Democracy in 
America> where he speaks of how free institutions combat the 
negative effects of the ubiquitous individualism of America.  He 
says that "[t]he law givers of America . . . thought it . . . 
right to give each part of the land its own political life so that 
there should be an infinite number of occasions for the citizens 
to act together and so . . . everyday they should feel that they 
depended on one another."  This motivates all citizens to take an 
interest in public affairs and the public good.127

Tocqueville states that while the physical circumstances are 
important in maintaining a democratic republic, and good laws are 
even more important, mores are the <most> important factor.128  It 
is to these, and generally to social-economic factors, that we now 
turn.

The one essentially economic factor that Tocqueville speaks of has 
been mentioned already:  material prosperity.  Prosperity, he 
indicates, has an important moderating effect on political 
behavior.  It tends to temper political extremism and to create an 
attachment to law and order.129

Several of the social factors Tocqueville points to involve 
attitudes in the citizenry (which include mores).  The others 
concern, essentially, the means by which the attitudes are shaped.  
The attitudes needed are a skill and a taste for freedom (which as 
noted, he links to the existence of communal institutions), "a 
restless spirit, immoderate desire for wealth, and an extreme love 
of independence,"130 great respect and even a willingness to 
sacrifice for the common good, and Tocqueville's famous "doctrine 
of self-interest properly understood."  This latter is defined as 
"enlightened self-love [which] continually leads . . . [Americans] 
to help one another and disposes them freely to give part of their 
time and wealth for the good of the state."  It is a kind of 
pragmatism which does not have high, noble ideas of virtue, but 
prompts many frequent small sacrifices and leads to lesser 
virtuous practices.  Also, "its discipline shapes a lot of 
orderly, temperate, careful, and self-controlled citizens."131  
Tocqueville is thus like Hamilton in believing that virtue and 
self interest can be made to coincide, Hamilton saying this about 
political leaders and Tocqueville of people in general.

Other factors are needed to shape these attitudes or, more 
accurately, shape them correctly, because if this is not done they 
can be perverted to the harm of the political community.  These 
factors are education, mores, and, especially, religion and the 
Christian religion in particular.

About education, Tocqueville contends that the U.S. Constitution 
assumes much diverse knowledge and discernment on the part of the 
governed.  "[I]t is only suited to a people long accustomed to 
manage its affairs, and one in which even the lowest ranks of 
society have an appreciation of political science."132  Stated 
more generally, "a democracy must . . . have reached a certain 
degree of civilization and enlightenment."133  While acknowledging 
the importance of education, however, Tocqueville insists that 
most people in a democratic republic do not need the same type of 
education as the sons of European aristocracy received.  Their 
education should not be a classical one, but scientific, 
commercial, and industrial.134

Tocqueville says that education strongly influences mores, which, 
again, he says are <the> critical factor.  Mores "can turn even 
the most unfavorable circumstances and worst laws to 
advantage."135  What he includes as "mores" are not only "habits 
of the heart," but "the different notions possessed by men, the 
various opinions current among them, and the sum of ideas that 
shape mental habits."136  Tocqueville explains the role of 
education in shaping mores:  "the instruction of the people [in 
the U.S.] powerfully contributes to support the democratic 
republic.  That will always be so . . . where the instruction 
which teaches the mind is not separated from the education which 
is responsible for mores."  Indeed, the relationship between 
private mores and habits and public life is emphasized by 
Tocqueville when he says that in the U.S., "education as a whole 
is directed toward the political life."137

Religion and particularly Christianity, for Tocqueville, seems to 
be the <most> important influence in shaping mores, however.  He 
writes that "in the United States religion . . . direct[s] mores, 
and by regulating domestic life it helps to regulate the state" 
and "should . . . be considered as the first of their [the 
Americans'] political institutions . . ."  Noting the "innumerable 
multitude of sects" in the U.S., he says that because "all preach 
the same morality in the name of God" (he was able to say in his 
time, as we cannot today, that "Christian morality is everywhere 
the same") it is not important that "all citizens should profess 
the true religion but that they should profess religion."138  He 
emphasizes the dangers a free people face if they become 
irreligious:

[D]oubt invades the highest faculties of the mind and half 
paralyzes all the rest.  Each man gets into the way of having 
nothing but confused and changing notions about the matters of 
greatest importance to himself and his fellows.  Opinions are ill-
defended or abandoned, and in despair of solving unaided the 
greatest problems of human destiny, men ignobly give up thinking 
about them.

Such a state inevitably enervates the soul, and relaxing the 
springs of the will prepares a people for bondage.

Then not only will they let their freedom be taken from them, but 
often they actually hand it over themselves.139

V. Summary and Conclusion

We can thus say that America's early political tradition, the 
political philosophers who influenced it, the Framers of our 
constitution, and such an astute commentator about our way of life 
as Tocqueville pointed to very definite ideas, conditions, 
practices, and institutional and legal arrangements that were 
needed to sustain a democratic republic.  If many of these 
elements were not present, or if certain individual ones were not, 
liberty would not be present or would not last and tyranny would 
quickly follow.  All of the elements discussed in this essay must 
be said to be important, but some _ because they are mentioned by 
so many of the sources examined or mentioned so frequently or are 
given special emphasis in the sources _ stand out as more crucial 
than others.  In the area of governmental institutions, the latter 
include:  separation of powers (perhaps the most frequently 
emphasized factor of any); the concomitant factor of checks and 
balances; an independent judiciary; and the existence of a federal 
system (even though the latter, in the writings considered, is 
referred to mostly as <helping> sustain a democratic republic in 
America, not as necessary in a general sense to sustain it).  The 
most important factors involving <both> institutional matters and 
democratic practice are the following:  that the makers of laws be 
subject to them; that there by, in some sense, a mixed government 
with both propertied interests and the people represented; that 
the presence of parties and factions to check each other and 
insure liberty is desirable; and that the laws must be accepted as 
preeminent.  In the category of strictly democratic principles and 
practice, the following can be pointed to:  the view that men have 
inherent rights and the purpose of government is to secure them 
and promote the common good; popular sovereignty with all the 
practices and principles that have been mentioned as falling under 
it including those relating to voting; a limitation of the 
franchise to those who demonstrate some kind of permanent 
attachment to the community; political liberty but with definite 
limitations; equality, but with modifications and limitations; and 
that the laws embody natural law or established principles of 
morality not made by men.  The guarantee of political and legal 
rights is especially important and certain of these rights, as 
follows, can be judged to be preeminent:  freedom of the press, 
freedom of religion, trial by jury, the protection of life, 
liberty, and property, <habeas corpus,> freedom of assembly, 
certain due process guarantees, and the prohibition of bills of 
attainder.  On the matter of the conduct of government, the 
practice which stands out is being cautious about the public 
credit and avoiding excessive public debt.  Finally, on the 
subject of social conditions, the following can be pointed to:  
the need for religion, education, morality (i.e., Christian moral 
beliefs), virtue, respect for law and the common good, a 
commitment to freedom, and a natural aristocracy of virtuous men 
to rule.  The importance generally of mores must also be stressed.

ENDNOTES

1 Martin Diamond, Winston Mills Fisk, and Herbert Garfinkle, <The 
Democratic Republic:  An Introduction to American National 
Government>, 2nd ed. (Chicago:  Rand McNally), pp. 89-91.

2 See, for example, Edward S. Corwin, <The "Higher Law" Background 
of American Constitutional Law> (Ithaca, N.Y.:  Cornell University 
Press), Pt. IV (Locke); Diamond, Fisk, and Garfinkle, pp. 125, 474 
(Locke); Alpheus Thomas Mason, <Free Government in the Making:  
Readings in American Political Thought,> 2nd ed. (N.Y.:  Oxford 
University Press, 1956), pp. 6-7 (Montesquieu); Russell Kirk, <The 
Roots of American Order> (LaSalle, Ill.:  Open Court, 1974), pp. 
347-358 (Montesquieu).  What has commonly been meant by "liberal 
democracy," of course, is the same characteristics as are usually 
associated with the American "democratic republic," as Diamond, 
<et. al>. define it:  there is a governmental order involving the 
election of a small number of representatives who form a 
legislative assembly _ this is the "democratic" aspect _ and there 
is also a commitment to maintaining certain constitutional and 
political principles and individual rights, such as "due process 
of law," equality before the law, freedom of speech and assembly, 
protection for minorities, and equal opportunities _ the "liberal" 
aspect.  (See David Robertson, <A Dictionary of Modern Politics> 
[Philadelphia:  Taylor and Francis, 1985], pp. 186-187.)

3 Locke's theory could also apply, for example, to a limited 
monarchy.  Indeed this was most directly what he was seeking to 
bring about in England.

4 John Locke, <Two Treatises of Government,> Peter Laslett, ed., 
rev. ed. (N.Y.: Cambridge University Press, 1960), IV, 22, 1-2, p. 
324.

5 Ibid., IV, 23, 6-7, p. 325, emphasis in the text.

6 Ibid., VIII, 13-16, p. 375, emphasis in the text.

7 Locke states the necessity for separation of powers in such 
passages as the following in the <Second Treatise>:  "For he being 
suppos'd to have all, both Legislative and Executive Power in 
himself alone, there is not Judge to be found, no Appeal lies open 
to anyone, who may fairly, and indifferently, and with Authority 
decide, and from whose decision relief and redress may be expected 
of any Injury or Inconveniency, that may be suffered from the 
Prince or by his Order" (VII, 91, 1-7, p. 370).

"But in Governments, where the <Legislative> is in one lasting 
Assembly always in being, or in one Man, as in Absolute 
Monarchies, there is danger still, that they will think themselves 
to have a distinct interest, from the rest of the Community; and 
so will be apt to increase their own Riches and Power, by taking, 
what they think fit, from the People" (XI, 138, 24-30, p. 407; 
emphasis in the text).

"Where the Legislative and Executive Powers are in distinct hands, 
(as they are in all moderated Monarchies, and well-framed 
Governments) there the good of the Society requires, that several 
things should be left to the discretion of him, that has the 
Executive Power" (XIV, 159, 1-5, p. 421).

8 Ibid., XIII, 150, 1-2, 9-10; 151, 1-4, pp. 413-414, emphasis in 
the text.

9 Ibid., XI, 134, 14-16, p. 401, emphasis in the text.

10 Ibid., 136, 20, 24-25, pp. 404-405.

11 Ibid., 142, 1-4, p. 409.

12 Ibid., 5-10, emphasis in the text.

13 Ibid., 138, 1-2, p. 406, emphasis in the text.

14 Ibid., 142, 11-20, p. 409, emphasis in the text.

15 Locke says that arbitrariness "is not much to be fear'd in 
Governments where the <Legislative> consists, wholly or in part, 
in Assemblies which are variable, whose Members upon the 
dissolution of the Assembly, are subjects under the common Laws of 
their Country, equally with the rest" (XI, 138, 19-23, p. 407, 
emphasis in the text).

16 Locke, XI, 140, 5-7, p. 408.

17 Ibid., XIV, 163, 10-12, p. 423, emphasis in the text.

18 Ibid., XIX, 212, 26, 29-30, p. 456, emphasis in the text.

19 Ibid., XIX, 220, 4, p. 459.

20 In Volume One, Book II of <The Spirit of the Laws>, which 
Montesquieu entitles "Of Laws Directly Derived from the Nature of 
Government" the section on the laws in a republic is entitled "Of 
the Republican Government, and the Laws in relation to Democracy."  
This combination of the terms "republican" and "democracy" and 
Montesquieu's ensuing discussion show that he has the same general 
idea of a "democratic republic" in mind as Diamond, Fisk, and 
Garfinkle (stated above) believe the Founding Fathers did.  See 
Baron de Montesquieu, <The Spirit of the Laws,> Thomas Nugent, 
trans. (N.Y.:  Hafner, 1949), One, II, p. 8.

21 Ibid., One, II, pp. 8, 9, 13; XI, pp. 151-152.

22 Ibid., II, p. 8.

23 Ibid., p. 9.

24 Ibid., pp. 11-12.

25 Ibid., p. 20.

26 Ibid., pp. 34, 40-41.

27 Ibid., XIX, p. 310.

28 Ibid., II, p. 45.

29 Ibid., p. 47.

30 Ibid., VIII, p. 110.

31 Ibid., p. 111.

32 Ibid., XI, p. 151.

33 Ibid., p. 150.

34 Ibid., II, p. 34.

35 Ibid., VIII, p. 120.  His reasons are set out in this passage:  
"It is natural for a republic to have only a small territory; 
otherwise it cannot long subsist.  In an extensive republic there 
are men of large fortunes, and consequently of less moderation; 
there are trusts too considerable to be placed in any single 
subject; he has interests of his own; he soon begins to think that 
he may be happy and glorious, by oppressing his fellow-citizens; 
and that he may raise himself to grandeur on the ruins of his 
country.

"In an extensive republic the public good is sacrificed to a 
thousand private views; it is subordinate to exceptions and 
depends on accidents.  In a small one, the interest of the public 
is more obvious, better understood, and more within the reach of 
every citizen; abuses have less extent, and, of course, are less 
protected." (Ibid.)

36 Constitution of Virginia _ 1776.  Source:  Ben Perley Poore, 
compiler, <The Federal and State Constitutions, Colonial Charters, 
and Other Organic Laws of the United States,> 2nd ed. (Washington:  
U.S. Government Printing Office, 1878), vol. 2, 1910-1912.

37 Constitution of Massachusetts _ 1780.  Source:  Ibid., vol. 1, 
p. 957.

38 Ibid., pp. 960-973.  It should be noted that the last of these 
principles _ a religious qualification for office _ was 
specifically rejected by the U.S. Constitution, which forbids 
religious tests.  Also, Bernard Bailyn writes that many state 
constitutional provisions after independence were seen as 
manifestations of the doctrine of separation of powers, but he 
gives a more accurate explanation of them below.  (See Bernard 
Bailyn, <The Origins of American Politics> [N.Y.:  Alfred A. 
Knopf, 1968], p. 79.)

39 Virginia Bill of Rights _ 1776, ibid., vol. 2, p. 1908.

40 Constitution of Massachusetts _ 1780, ibid., vol. 1, p. 957.

41 Virginia Bill of Rights _ 1776, ibid., vol. 2, pp. 1908-1909 
and Constitution of Massachusetts _ 1780, ibid., vol. 1, pp. 956-
957.  This last quote is from the latter, p. 957.

42 Virginia Bill of Rights _ 1776, p. 957.

43 Stephen M. Krason, <Abortion:  Politics, Morality, and the 
Constitution _ A Critical Study of Roe v. Wade and Doe v. Bolton 
and a Basis for Change> (Lanham, Md.:  University Press of 
America, 1984), pp. 253-254.  Cf. Roscoe Pound, <The Development 
of Constitutional Guarantees of Liberty> (New Haven, Conn.:  Yale 
University Press, 1957), pp. 83-89.

44 Krason, pp. 254-255.  Even though the right to a grand jury 
indictment or presentment appeared in only a minority of state 
constitutions and bills of rights, the view that the grand jury 
was an important defense of individual liberties and check on 
prosecutors and other officials was apparently widespread in 
colonial America.  (See George Dargo, <Roots of the Republic:  A 
New Perspective on Early American Constitutionalism> [N.Y.:  
Praeger, 1974], p. 70.)

45 Krason, pp. 256-257.  See the book for references.

46 It should be noted that I follow Charles A. Beard's assessment 
of the members of the Convention "whose character, ability, 
diligence and regularity of attendance separately or in 
combination, made them the dominant element."  (Beard, "The 
Supreme Court _ Usurper of Grantee," in <Essays in Constitutional 
Law,> Robert G. McCloskey, ed. [N.Y.:  Alfred A. Knopf, 1962], p. 
27.  Originally published in <Political Science Quarterly>, vol. 
27, p. 1 [1912].)

47 Bailyn, pp. 131-135.

48 Ibid., p. 79.

49 Dargo, p. 52.

50 Ibid.

51 Ibid., p. 51.

52 Bailyn, p. 146.

53 Dargo, p. 48.

54 Bailyn, p. 86.

55 Ibid., p. 81.

56 Ibid.

57 Ibid., pp. 124-127.

58 Ibid., pp. 87-88.

59 Ibid., p. 81.

60 Ibid., p. 125.

61 Ibid., pp. 125-127, quoting the New York and Pennsylvania 
writers without providing their names.

62 Federalist 10 (Madison), Alexander Hamilton, John Jay, James 
Madison, <The Federalist> (N.Y.:  The Modern Library, n.d.), pp. 
54-62.

63 Alexander Hamilton, "Speech on Compromises," in <The Works of 
Alexander Hamilton>, vol. II, John C. Hamilton, ed. (N.Y.:  
Charles S. Francis, 1850), p. 430.

64 John Dickinson, "Letters of Fabius on the Federal Constitution" 
Letter IV, April 10, 1788, in <Pamphlets on the Constitution of 
the United States>, Paul Leicester Ford, ed. (N.Y.:  Burt 
Franklin, n.d.), p. 182.

65 Edmund Randolph, "Letter on the Federal Constitution," October 
16, 1787, in Ford, p. 268.

66 Federalist 47 (Madison), <The Federalist,> p. 313.

67 See Saul K. Padover, ed., <The Complete Jefferson> (N.Y.:  
Duell, Sloan and Pearce, 1943), pp. 106, 114.

68 Jefferson, letter to Madison, December 20, 1787, ibid., p. 123.

69 See Marvin Myers, ed., <The Mind of the Founder:  Sources of 
the Political Thought of James Madison,> pp. 304, 502-503.

70 James Wilson, "Substance of an Address to a Meeting of the 
Citizens of Philadelphia," October 16, 1787, in Ford, p. 156.

71 John Adams, "Defence of the Constitutions of the United States 
of America," in <The Works of John Adams>, vol. 6 (Boston:  Little 
& Brown, 1851), pp. 65, 78, 91, 105-106.

72 Madison, "Remarks on Mr. Jefferson's Draught of A Constitution 
[for Virginia]" sent to John Brown, October 12, 1788, in Myers, p. 
56.

73 Hamilton, remarks in the New York ratification convention, June 
24, 1788, in <The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the 
Adoption of the Federal Constitution>, Jonathan Eliot, ed. 
(Philadelphia:  J.B. Lippincott, 1901), vol. II, p. 302.

74 Hamilton, "Speech on Compromises," in J.C. Hamilton, vol. II, 
pp. 437, 444, and "Speech on the Senate of the United States" in 
the New York ratification convention, 1788, in ibid., p. 453.  It 
is worth noting that George Washington, in his famous Farewell 
Address of 1796, with the first years of actual experience with 
the Constitution just behind and theory thus converted into 
practice, reaffirms in the strongest terms the essentiality of 
separation of powers and check and balances.  (See Washington, 
<Farewell Address>, General Society, Sons of the Revolution, 
booklet edition [N.Y.:  1963, 1982], p. 24.)

75 Federalist 78 (Hamilton), <The Federalist>, p. 504.

76 Hamilton, "Speech on Compromise," in J.C. Hamilton, vol. II, p. 
444 and remarks in the New York ratification convention, June 21, 
1788, in Eliot, vol. II, pp. 257, 258.

77 Jefferson, "Draft of a Constitution for Virginia," in Padover, 
p. 112.

78 Madison, speech of August 7, 1787 at the Convention, redone in 
1821 for planned posthumous publication of his Convention notes, 
in Myers, p. 506.

79 Ibid., pp. 507-508.

80 Jefferson, letter to Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1916, in 
Padover, p. 288; Adams, "Defence" in <Works>, vol. 6, p. 74; John 
Dickinson, "Letters of Fabius on the Federal Constitution," letter 
II, April 10, 1788, in Ford, p. 171.  Hamilton makes the point 
about Senate terms being long in his speech in the New York 
ratification convention, June 24, 1788, in Eliot, Vol. II, p. 307.  
The extent to which the idea of short terms and frequent elections 
was accepted at the Framers' time is seen by the fact it is 
emphasized also by such Anti-Federalists as Melancton Smith and 
John Lansing, Jr. in the New York ratification debate (Eliot, vol. 
II, pp. 249, 295) and in the writings against the Constitution by 
Elbridge Gerry, see "Observations on the new Constitution . . ." 
in Ford, pp. 9, 11, 12.

81 Hamilton, N.Y. ratification debate, June 21, 1788, in Eliot, 
vol. II, p. 257.  Jefferson concurs with this.  See his First 
Inaugural Address, in Padover, p. 386 and his letter to Samuel 
Kercheval, July 12, 1816, in Padover, p. 288.

82 Diamond, Fisk, and Garfinkle, p. 10.

83 See, for example, Charles A. Beard, <An Economic Interpretation 
of the Constitution> (N.Y.:  Macmillan, 1913); Staughton Lyrd, 
<Class Conflict, Slavery and the United States Constitution> 
(Indianapolis:  Bobbs-Merrill, 1967); and Michael Parenti, 
<Democracy for the Few>, 3rd ed. (N.Y.:  St. Martin's, 1980).

84 Jefferson, letter to Samuel Kercheval, in Padover, pp. 287-288.

85 Hamilton, Speech on Compromises, ibid., in J.C. Hamilton, vol. 
II, p. 453.

86 Madison, letter to unknown correspondent, 1833, in Myers, p. 
530.

87 Adams, "Defence," in <Works>, vol. 6, p. 64.

88 Edmund Randolph, speech in the Virginia ratification 
convention, June 16, 1788, in Eliot, Vol. III, p. 84.

89 Washington, p. 16.

90 Jefferson, letter to Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1816, in 
Padover, p. 289.

91 Jefferson, First Inaugural Address in Padover, p. 384.

92 Adams, "Defence," in <Works>, vol. 6, p. 197 (military); 
Dickinson, in Ford, letter IV, p. 186 (taxation); Hamilton, 
"Speech on compromises" in J.C. Hamilton, vol. II, p. 430 
(taxation and military); Jefferson, First Inaugural Address, in 
Padover, p. 386 (military and drafts of Declaration of 
Independence and Proposed Constitution for Virginia, 1776 (by 
implication, taxation), in Padover, pp. 31, 104.

93 Adams, "Defence," in <Works>, vol. 4, p. 295.

94 Ibid., vol. 6, p. 56.

95 Ibid.  See also vol. 4, pp. 293-295.

96 See Washington, p. 18, and Jefferson, First Inaugural Address, 
in Padover, p. 386.

97 See <The Federalist,> pp. 141-146, 153-158, 454-463.

98 Washington, p. 26.

99 Jefferson, in Padover, p. 386.

100 Jefferson, letter to Kercheval, ibid., pp. 290-291.

101 Jefferson, First Inaugural Address, ibid., p. 386.

102 Ibid.

103 Washington, p. 12.

104 Ibid., pp. 30, 32.

105 Jefferson, First Inaugural Address, ibid., p. 386.

106 See Adams, "Defence," in <Works,> vol. 6, p. 208; Washington, 
p. 16.

107 Adams, ibid.

108 See Jefferson, letter to Kercheval, in Padover, p. 288 and 
Madison, Federalist 57, in <The Federalist,> p. 373.

109 Madison, ibid.

110 Jefferson, letter to Madison, December 20, 1787, ibid., p. 
123.

111 Hamilton, "Speech on the Senate" in New York ratification 
convention, 1788, in J.C. Hamilton, vol II, p. 453.

112 Jefferson, "A Bill for the More General Diffusion of 
Knowledge," in Padover, p. 1048.

113 Jefferson, letter to Thomas Law, Esq., June 13, 1814, in 
Padover, pp. 1032-1034.

114 Jefferson, letter to Madison, December 20, 1787, in Padover, 
p. 123.

115 Madison, letter to W.T. Barry, Aug. 4, 1822, in James Madison, 
<The Forging of American Federalism:  Selected Writings,> Saul K. 
Padover, ed. (N.Y.:  Harper and Row [Harper Torchbooks], 1953), p. 
313.

116 Washington, p. 26.

117 Adams, "Defence," in <Works,> vol. 6, pp. 197-198.

118 Washington, p. 24.

119 Jefferson, letter to John Adams, Oct. 28, 1813, in Padover, p. 
283.

120 Ibid., p. 284.

121 Alexis de Tocqueville,  <Democracy in America>, J.P. Mayer, 
ed. (Garden City, N.Y.:  Doubleday [Anchor], 1969), book one, part 
II, pp. 280-281, 306.

122Ibid., one, I, p. 170.

123 Ibid., one, II, p. 287 and one, I, pp. 99-105.  Tocqueville 
makes clear that judges were not intended to legislate in the U.S. 
when he says, "If he [a judge] pronounces upon a law without 
reference to a particular case, he steps right beyond his sphere 
and invades that of the legislature" (p. 100).

124 Ibid., one, II, p. 307.

125 Ibid., one, II, p. 287.

126 Ibid., one, III, p. 279.

127 Ibid., two, II, p. 511.

128 Ibid., one, II, p. 307.

129 See ibid., one, II pp. 287-288.

130 Ibid., one, II, p. 284.

131 Ibid., two, II, pp. 526-527.

132 Ibid., one, I, pp. 164-165.

133 Ibid., one, II, p. 225.

134 Ibid., two, II, pp. 476-477.

135 Ibid., one, II, p. 308.

136 Ibid., one, II, p. 287.

137 Ibid., one, II, pp. 304-305.

138 Ibid., one, II, pp. 290-291.

139 Ibid., two, I, p. 444.

Stephen M. Krason earned his Ph.D. in political science and his 
J.D. from the State University of New York at Buffalo.  He is 
Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of 
Steubenville and Adjunct Research Associate of the Intercollegiate 
Studies Institute. 

This article was taken from the Fall 1992 issue of "Faith & 
Reason". Subscriptions available from Christendom Press, 2101 
Shenandoah Shores Road, Ft. Royal, VA 22630, 703-636-2900, Fax 
703-636-1655. Published quarterly at $20.00 per year.

Copyright (c) 1996 EWTN

-------------------------------------------------------

   Provided courtesy of:

        Eternal Word Television Network
        PO Box 3610
        Manassas, VA 22110
        Voice: 703-791-2576
        Fax: 703-791-4250
        Data: 703-791-4336
        Web: http://www.ewtn.com
        FTP: ewtn.com
        Telnet: ewtn.com
        Email address: sysop@ ewtn.com

   EWTN provides a Catholic online 
   information and service system.

-------------------------------------------------------